Tuesday, 1 April 2025

Are Panpsychism and String Theory Unscientific or Non-Scientific?

 “We must distinguish between being non-scientific and being unscientific. [] philosophy [perhaps panpsychism and/or string theory] is a subject which is almost certainly of its very nature non-scientific. We must not jump from this purely negative statement to the conclusion that it has the positive defect of being unscientific.” — C.D. Broad

“‘Unscientific’ sounds more negative. It implies that something is pseudoscience. (A scam that is pretending to be science but not using the scientific method properly.) ‘Non-scientific’ is more neutral and might be used to describe parascience. (Fields of study that are not science or math but still valuable in their own way, such as law and history.).”

— See source here.

Let’s start off with a passage from the English philosopher C.D. Broad (1887–1971):


“We must distinguish between being non-scientific and being un-scientific. What I have admitted is that philosophy is a subject which is almost certainly of its very nature non-scientific. We must not jump from this purely negative statement to the conclusion that it has the positive defect of being unscientific. The latter term can be properly used only when a subject, which is capable of scientific treatment, is treated in a way which ignores or conflicts with the principles of scientific method.”

[As found in Broad’s paper, ‘Philosophy’, in Inquiry I.]

Interestingly, C.D. Broad had telekinesis, mind-reading and backwards causation in mind when he wrote the words above. [See this article on Broad in Psi Encyclopedia.] That alone shows us how problematic the distinction between x being unscientific and x being non-scientific is. What’s more, this distinction may allow too much leeway for the subjects under discussion (i.e., even when it comes to what’s non-scientific, never mind what’s unscientific).

In any case, if we forget telekinesis, mind-reading, etc., it’s feasible that both string theory and panpsychism can be non-scientific without thereby also being unscientific. However, there’s an obvious difference here. As stated, string theory is a science and panpsychism isn’t. Thus, if string theory is either non-scientific or unscientific, then that’s a problem. Perhaps panpsychism, on the other hand, is only problematic if it’s unscientific.

[I believe that it’s fair to say that the strong term “pseudoscientific” doesn’t apply to either panpsychism or string theory… Of course, some readers may disagree with that!]

So let’s speak in broader terms here.

Is Panpsychism Unscientific or Non-Scientific?

Panpsychism is a philosophical theory, whereas string theory is part of science. (Some — perhaps even many — physicists question the scientific status of string theory. See here.) Nonetheless, some of the philosophical (i.e., not scientific) problems which both face are similar.

Of course, panpsychist philosophers don’t claim that panpsychism is an actual science — or even that it’s scientific.

Philosophy itself isn’t a science. Consequently, that must mean that panpsychism isn’t a science.

(Some kinds of philosophy are classed as being “scientific”, without thereby also being actual examples of science. See here.)

Despite the words above, many panpsychists (as with various other metaphysicians) claim that panpsychism must still be respectful of physics. [See here and here.] Alternatively, they say that it shouldn’t (directly) contradict anything in science. Indeed, because panpsychism deals with “intrinsic nature”, then — almost by definition! — it can be said that it can’t contradict anything in physics.

To return to the difference between non-scientific and unscientific.

If we say that panpsychism is non-scientific (to quote Broad again), then

[w]e must not jump from this purely negative statement to the conclusion that it has the positive defect of being unscientific”.

The last statement from Broad is very helpful in this context. Let me re-quote it:

“The latter term [‘unscientific’] can be properly used only when a subject, which is capable of scientific treatment, is treated in a way which ignores or conflicts with the principles of scientific method.”

This means that if panpsychism deals with a subject “which is [in]capable of scientific treatment” (and which “is [also] treated in a way which ignores or conflicts with the principles of scientific method”), then we may have a philosophical problem. The point here is that panpsychists will simply claim that panpsychism has nothing whatsoever to do “with the principles of scientific method”.

Some philosophers may also claim that panpsychism and science are two non-overlapping worlds or language games.

In detail. This parallels — at least to some extent — the Wittgensteinian claim that science and religion don’t contradict each other because they’re dealing with different phenomena.

This means that science and religion are — in the words of Steven Jay Gould — “non-overlapping magisteria”.

Alternatively, some philosophers may claim that science and religion sometimes deal with the same phenomena, though in very different ways.

On this Wittgensteinian view, then, religion is non-scientific, not unscientific.

So does this also mean that panpsychism and physics are also non-overlapping magisteria? So, if that is the case, then how can they contradict one another?

That said, I would assume that panpsychism surely can’t be in an equivalent position as religion vis-à-vis its relation to science (or to physics).

So some of the claims above may be too convenient for panpsychism.

Take the following position:

i) If physics states that there are no “intrinsic properties” (certainly if it claims that micro-entities don’t have “phenomenal properties”),

ii) then panpsychism does indeed “conflict with the principles” of physics.

The problem is, however, that panpsychists (as well as some physicists) claim that physics simply “ignores” intrinsic properties. In other words, physics has no position at all on such things. As the philosopher Philip Goff once put it:

“This [panpsychist] argument presses us to the conclusion that there must be more to physical entities than what they do: physical things must also have an ‘intrinsic nature’…”

Elsewhere, Goff wrote:

[G]iven that physics is restricted to telling us only about the behaviour of physical entities — electrons, quarks and indeed spacetime itself — it leaves us completely in the dark about their intrinsic nature. Physics tells us what matter does, but not what it is.”

Some (perhaps many) physicists, on the other hand, will simply claim that intrinsic properties don’t exist. Thus, we can conclude by saying that physics as a whole — as stated — doesn’t have a universal or systematic position on intrinsic properties.

The other much broader point which has to be made is that the scientific criticisms of panpsychism can also be applied to many (actually, most) other philosophical theories. Indeed, the entirety of metaphysics has been said to be suspect from a scientific point of view — at least according to some scientists and philosophers at certain points in history!

All this means that panpsychism’s relationship with science is far from being unique.

Yet philosophy can indeed be unscientific, rather than simply non-scientific.

What about string theory?

Is String Theory Unscientific or Non-Scientific?

See my ‘Physicist Peter Woit on the Sociology of String Theory’.

A simple — and perhaps naïve — example of the problem of string theory’s scientific credentials relates to the question as to what is and what isn’t observable and/or testable.

If what can be observed and/or tested — or can be in observed and/or tested (as it’s often put) “in principle” — is ignored or rejected, then surely that would be an unscientific position to take. However, even within science, many things are unobservable (e.g., quarks, protons, the iron core at the centre of the earth, distant galaxies, fields and forces, etc.). Some things are even unobservable in principle (e.g., the past, numbers, laws, universals, perhaps other minds, etc.).

All that clearly has relevance to both string theory and panpsychism.

Indeed, most (or all) of the claims of metaphysics (even those claims about things which are observable and/or testable) are still primarily about things which aren’t observable and/or testable.

This also means that if science has no problem with panpsychism (or even accepts the fruitfulness of research into it), then that would also fit in well with the “theoretical pluralism” referred to earlier.

Now what about string theory and the non-scientific/unscientific bifurcation?

We can say that because of the current state of play, many of the claims and theories of string theory aren’t (to use C.D. Broad’s words again) “capable of scientific treatment”. (Not only because of the experimental limitations brought about by the deficiencies and limitations of contemporary technology.) Nonetheless, that doesn’t necessarily also mean that string theory “conflicts with the principles of science”.

Of course, it can now be said that if string theory’s claims aren’t capable of scientific treatment, then how can they still be scientific? However, couldn’t this question also be asked of many 19th century and 20th century theories (in physics)? That is, many theories were created before the evidence, experiments or tests were in. So does that also mean that such claims and theories were unscientific?

What’s more, if the experiments and evidence did come later, then surely we can’t still say that such formerly untested theories were unscientific.



Monday, 31 March 2025

William James on Truth… According to Richard Rorty

 

Many 20th century philosophers set themselves the task of defining (or redefining) the words “true” and “truth”. They wanted to see how these words were actually used in their many and varied contexts. This meant that such philosophers didn’t want to embark on the ancient — and perhaps fruitless — philosophical journey of discovering “the nature of truth” — as if truth were a pre-existing entity (or property) which has a determinate and circumscribed nature regardless of how individuals, groups and societies use the words “truth” and “true”…

However, let’s go back in time to the 19th century here and start with the American philosopher and psychologist William James (1842–1910).

The American philosopher Richard Rorty (who died in 2007) put James’s position in the following way:

“If we have the notion of ‘justified’, [then] we don’t need that of ‘truth’.”

Rorty went on to claim that James believed that the word

“‘[t]rue’ must mean something like ‘justifiable’”.

On this reading, then, it seems that we could (or should) literally erase the word “true” from our language, and simply substitute it with the word “justifiable”. Yet if “true” actually means “justifiable”, then there’s simply no need to erase the word “true” at all.

What’s more, as a pragmatist, James wouldn’t have deemed the erasure of the word “true” as a viable or sensible option. In other words, the everyday uses of the words “true” and “truth” have pragmatic utility. However, just don’t reify (or Platonise) them.

William James wasn’t really setting up a literal identity between truth and justification. In other words, it didn’t make sense to view these terms in the abstract.

Let’s now spell out James’s (possible) position:

A true statement is a statement which has been justified (or whose utterance is justifiable).

As can be seen, the statement above is about other statements: it’s not a statement about the physical or metaphysical world.

So what about the the thing (or the property) truth?

Well, we can bite the bullet and argue that truth is indeed an abstract property. It’s only a property of certain statements… However, even this isn’t really the case because the predicate “is true” (or the word “true”) is applied to certain statements — it’s not an actual property of those statements themselves. (This is vaguely equivalent to putting a dress on a mannequin: the mannequin and the particular dress aren’t the same thing.) Thus, outside the context of those statements we deem to be true (or which have been justified), perhaps there is no property that is truth.

Despite all the above, Rorty still believed that James was in “error”. He continued:

“The error is to assume that ‘true’ needs a definition [ ].”

Rorty wasn’t taking truth to be a thing or even a property. Instead, “truth” (or “true”) is a word which human beings use about certain statements. So beyond what human beings say about these particular statements, there is no thing (or property) which is truth.

More precisely, when we say that statement S “is true”, this is simply an affirmation of that statement. That said, we may still believe (to get back to James’s position) that statement S is justified (or justifiable), and therefore we’ll go straight ahead and affirm it…

Of course, we needn’t necessarily be committed to James’s particular stress on justification, let alone be committed to believing that the word “true” can be substituted with the word “justified”.

Rorty then went on to claim that idealists too made a similar (or the same) error about the word “truth” (or the property truth). He wrote:

“This was a form of the idealist error of inferring from

‘We can make no sense of the notion of truth as correspondence’

to

‘Truth must consist in ideal coherence.’ [ ].”

So the notion of “truth as correspondence” (which idealists had a problem with) fails because, again, if there’s no thing (or property) truth in the first place, then truth can’t be “ideal coherence” either. [There are, surprisingly, many other problems with the intuitively plausible truth-as-correspondence idea. See here.]

So there are two things which should be noted here:

(1) It is certain statements (i.e., not facts, properties, things, states of affair, etc.) that are true. (Truth isn’t a thing or a property separate from certain statements.)
(2) By which criteria do we decide that statements are true — even if we accept that truth is not a thing or a property?





 

Friday, 21 March 2025

Explaining Qualia?

 

“The problem of explaining these phenomenal qualities is just the problem of explaining consciousness. This is the really hard part of the mind-body problem.”

— David Chalmers [See source here.]

What does the Australian philosopher David Chalmers mean by the the word “explaining” (as in “explaining consciousness”)? That is, what is it to explain qualia or to explain consciousness?

What would an explanation of phenomenal qualities look like — even if there is one… somewhere?

This isn’t to say that there is — or there isn’t — an explanation: it’s simply to ask what such an explanation would look like.

David Chalmers

More particularly, it can be suspected that no explanation would ever satisfy David Chalmers… or any other non-physicalist for that matter. And that could quite possibly be because there can be no explanation which pleases everyone — at least not of the kind that Chalmers demands.

Perhaps this is, after all, a bogus problem.

What does that mean?

It means that the Hard Problem isn’t a problem at all. [I’ve gone into this in greater detail elsewhere. See here and here.] Either that, or no explanation would ever satisfy all those philosophers who’re demanding an explanation.

More technically, would such an explanation of phenomenal properties be an explanation from a first-person (or subjective) point of view?…

Well, that wouldn’t satisfy many scientists and philosophers.

Okay.

Would such an explanation be a neuroscientific (or behaviourist or functionalist) explanation?…

Well, that wouldn’t satisfy Chalmers and many other philosophers.

So what about uniting these physical (or functional) accounts with first-person accounts?

Is that possible?

Well, Chalmers gave it a try with his notion of “structural coherence”.

Anil Seth

But, firstly, the British neuroscientist Anil Seth (kind of) hinted at structural coherence when he recently wrote the following words:

[I]f we instead move beyond establishing correlations to discover explanations that connect properties of neural mechanisms to properties of subjective experience [] then this gap will narrow and might even disappear entirely.”

David Chalmers himself tackled this issue many years ago — i.e., in 1995. So, 29 years ago, Chalmers wrote:

“This is a principle of coherence between the *structure of consciousness* and the *structure of awareness*.”

Yet, later, Chalmers also notes the problems here:

“This principle reflects the central fact even though cognitive processes do not conceptually entail facts about conscious experience [and] not all properties of experience are structural properties.”

Simply put: we can say that if x is coherent with y, then x and y still can’t be one and the same thing. Thus, we don’t have any literal identity here…

So doesn’t the Hard Problem remain?

What about the many and varied verbal reports of consciousness and/or qualia?

Daniel Dennett

A person may verbally report his experience/s of particular phenomenal properties, and that might well have satisfied, say, Daniel Dennett. [See here.] However, and so the argument will go, such reports would still only be verbal reports of qualia — not accounts of qualia themselves (whatever that may mean!).

What’s more, perhaps even if there were such an account of qualia themselves, then it still couldn’t — almost by definition — be united with a scientific account.

Thus, there’s both a definitional gap and an “explanatory gap” between scientific accounts of phenomenal properties, and the subjective (or first-person) accounts of the (supposedly) very same things — and never the twain shall meet.

Chalmers will argue that the (or his) Hard Problem remains.

The upshot here is that David Chalmers will never be satisfied with the accounts of Daniel Dennett, (many) scientists, etc. And Dennett and these scientists will never be satisfied with the accounts of Chalmers and the “mysterians”.

Again, there’s a large gap between the two positions.

What’s more, even those much-advocated structural correlations (i.e., between neural states and conscious states), and Chalmers’ own (stronger?) notion of structural coherence, will never bridge that gap…

Perhaps nothing will.

Perhaps nothing can.