i) Introduction
ii) Knowledge?
iii) Knowledge
By Description & Knowledge by Acquaintance
iv) Mary's
New Abilities
v) Knowing
How & Knowing That
vi) Conclusion
************************
Mary
“doesn't know what it's like to see red”. This argument has
nothing to do with imagination
(or Mary’s inability to imagine red). As Frank Jackson puts
it:
“Powers of imagination are not to the point”. This is about
Mary’s knowledge
(or lack thereof), not her imagination. More precisely, “she would
not know” what it's like to experience red.
More
to the point,
“if
physicalism is true, she would know; and no great powers of
imagination would be called for”.
Knowledge?
The
first response to this is to ask what Jackson meant by the word
“knowledge” (or by the words “knowledge of red”). This seems
like an odd use of the word “know”. How would Mary (or anyone
else for that matter) know
what
red is like? What is the epistemology of knowing
red?
Even if Mary could sense
red: could she also know
red (or what red is)? Could she (or anyone else) be wrong
about what is or isn't red (i.e., without inter-communal responses)?
Is
Jackson’s conclusion correct? That is:
i)
If physicalism is true
ii)
then Mary would know what red is.
Firstly,
Jackson argues that given Mary’s “fantastic grasp of
neurophysiology and everything else physical” she couldn't thereby
work out the last phenomenal part of red “by making some more
purely logical inferences”. Mary can't, then, infer the phenomenal
from the purely physical - no matter how complete and exact her
physical knowledge is.
Knowledge
By Description & Knowledge By Acquaintance
Jackson
then makes a distinction which has often been made in various areas
of philosophy: the distinction between “knowledge
by description”
and “knowledge
by acquaintance”.
Presumably Mary had knowledge
by description before
she was let out of her black-and-white room. After she was let out,
then she had knowledge
by acquaintance.
In other words, her previous complete descriptions
of red weren't enough. On freeing, she also became acquainted
with
red (not only with red’s physical “supervenience
base”,
as Jaegwon Kim puts it).
Does
this also mean that phenomenal
red
literally can't be described? This is a position which has been long
accepted by many philosophers. That's why colours (or “colour
words”) are taught (so
the argument goes)
purely by ostension
– by the teacher pointing to something red and then saying to the
student, “This is red.” However, if red is (in effect) purely
phenomenal, and taught by ostension, then how can Mary (or anyone
else) have knowledge
of red?
Mary
Acquired New Abilities, Not New Knowledge
I've
questioned Jackson’s use of the notion of knowledge. So too does
David
Lewis
and
Laurence
Nemirow.
They do so by distinguishing knowing
(or learning) that something is red from acquiring “a
certain representational or imaginative ability”.
How can the sudden new experience of red (outside the black-and-white
room) be a knowledge
of red?
How does Mary learn something new? She experiences something new;
though she doesn't learn something new or acquire new knowledge.
However,
something new does happen to Mary. As stated, she acquires a certain
representational or imaginative ability.
Presumably that ability is to recognise red on further occasions (or
to distinguish red from other colours). Though how would she know
that it's red unless someone else tells her that's the case? This
would be especially relevant if Mary's new experience of red was
sudden and had no direct connection to her previous examinations of
red’s physical micro-structure. Outside the room she would see
something new; though how would she know that it's red? Indeed how
would she have known that it was a colour of any description?
Knowing
How & Knowing That
Earlier
I commented on Jackson’s use of the knowledge
by description
and knowledge
by acquaintance
distinction. Now he brings in the “knowing
how”
and the “knowing
that”
distinction (as used by David Lewis).
Mary
now knows how to recognise red. She has that “ability”. Does she
know
that it's red? Not if, as argued, she has no new knowledge
of red
at all. And even with such knowledge, she would still require
third-person help (as it were) to tell her that the red wall outside
is indeed red.
We
can join up the two oppositions here:
knowledge
by acquaintance - knowledge how
knowledge
by description - knowledge that
However,
according to this discussion, neither knowledge
by acquaintance
nor knowing
how
are, in fact, examples of knowledge
(strictly speaking). Only knowledge
by description
and knowing
that
are true examples of knowledge. Alternatively, perhaps we can't have
one without the other. That is:
i) We can't have knowledge how without knowledge that. Or,ii) We can't have knowledge that without knowledge how.
Mary
needs knowledge
that red is red
before she can learn how to distinguish red from other colours.
Alternatively, she must know something
in order to know that it's a colour or that she has had a new
experience outside her room. To know that red
is red,
she must know what red looks like. How does this work for the other
distinction? Thus:
i) We can't have knowledge by acquaintance without knowledge by description. Or,ii) We can't have knowledge by description without knowledge by acquaintance.
This
works in a similar way to the above - and for similar reasons. How do
we know we're acquainted
with
something (an x)
without the help of some form of description? How do we know we're
now acquainted with red without some kind of ostensive definition (or
some other kind of help)? We may know that we're acquainted with
something new; though not that it's red or even that it's a colour of
any kind. Alternatively, red can't be described to us in order to
give us knowledge
that
without our also being acquainted
in some way with phenomenal red. Without being acquainted with
something, we wouldn’t know what it is that's being described.
Yet
what if both distinctions are false disjunctures between ostensibly
two alternatives? Perhaps this is like Ned
Block’s
distinction
between
“phenomenal
consciousness”
and “access
consciousness”.
The difference here is that Block admits that in this case you may
not be able to have the one without the other. Nevertheless, this
shouldn't stop us making the distinction because it's still, after
all, an acceptable distinction.
Conclusion
The
important conclusion to all this is
that
“a
physicalist can admit that Mary acquires something very significant
of a knowledge kind – which can hardly be denied – without
admitting that this shows that her earlier factual knowledge is
defective”.
Physicalists
aren't, then, denying that extra
little something.
They only deny the increase in Mary’s knowledge.
Thus it's strange that Jackson (at least at this point in his career)
still insisted in using the word “knowledge” - suitably reduced
to his “of
a knowledge kind”.
What did he mean by that? A kind
of
knowledge is still an example
of knowledge, isn’t it?
Thus
perhaps all this depends on what Jackson and physicalists mean by the
word “knowledge”!
References
Block,
Ned, 'On
a Confusion About a Function of Consciousness' (1995)
Jackson,
Frank, 'What
Mary Didn't Know'
(1986)
Lewis,
David, 'What
Experience Teaches'
(1990).
No comments:
Post a Comment