[This
piece is an account of parts of James Ladyman and Don Ross's book,
Every
Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized.]
***********************
Two simple things pose a problem for anyone wanting to embrace ontic structural realism: 1) The various two-slit experiments. 2) Problems with terminology.
Firstly,
let's discuss the well-known two-slit experiments.
1
The
Firing of Single Particles
A photon (for example) is a single quantum of light. In fact it's referred to as a "light quantum" or as a “light particle”. It's also the case that single particles have been fired (in double-slit experiments) at relatively long intervals between each firing!
In terms of detail, let's forget here when particles-in-the-plural have been fired (e.g., by J.J. Thomson, Ernest Rutherford, Ernest Walton, etc.) and concentrate on the firing of single particles.
Take Pier Giorgio Merli, Giulio Pozzi and Gianfranco Missiroli who did so in the 1970s in order to demonstrate what's called “interference”. And, in 1989, Akira Tonomura and his colleagues also fired electrons one at a time at the Hitachi research laboratories. Then Herman Batelaan and his team did the same thing and the results were published in 2013.
(Alain
Aspect's well-known experiment is actually said to have used
many pairs of photons to demonstrate
“spooky action at a distance”
or “entanglement”.)
However, were single particles really fired in these experiments?
It's
worth noting here that even atoms don't have rigid boundaries (or
really any boundaries at all ). This is even more the case with
particles. Thus these facts must surely raise particular questions as
to how single particles can be fired in experiments. Having said
that, this may well only be a technical (rather than scientific or
philosophical) question.
Of course something must be fired.
Though is it the case that some individual thing is fired each time? Perhaps, instead, only spatiotemporal chunks (or spatiotemporal slices) of fields are fired. What can't be fired, however, are what philosophers call “individuals”, as we shall now see.
Terminology
The word “thing” is an everyday word. It can applied to anything (or to any thing). The word “individual” (as used by James Ladyman and other philosophers) is a philosophical technical term. And, finally, the word “particle” is mainly used within a scientific context. (It's true that Isaac Newton's use of of the word “particle” is at odds with many 20th-century uses; though all such uses are still fundamentally scientific.)
Particles (such as electrons) can't be individuals (as most philosophers see individuals) simply because all the particles of a specific kind share all their properties (i.e., spin, mass, charge, etc.). So, semantically, these properties can't be seen as intrinsic or essential because particles don't actually have contingent properties. However, that's unless we bring in the relations which particles have with other things/particles or with fields! And this is where ontic structural realism comes in.
Thus, on a philosophical reading, particles - by definition - can't be individuals. Every particle of a given kind has the same properties – that's if, again, we rule out relational or spatial properties. A single particle, then, isn't like a single human person, who can easily be distinguished from other human persons. Indeed a single human person may well have both essential and contingent properties. (That will depend on one's metaphysical position.)
In
addition, what Ladyman, Ross and other philosophers call “identity
dependence” and “existence dependence” doesn't seem to
automatically rule out an entity being an individual. Or, if
it does, we'd still need to know why that's the case. And then
there's the added problem of using a philosophical technical term
(i.e., “individual”) and then foisting it into discussions of the
particles of physics.
This
also applies to Ladyman and Ross's term “self-subsistent”. If
that term is taken literally, then has any entity in the entire
history of the universe ever been self-subsistent? Of course
all that will depend on what each philosopher who uses that term
actually takes it to mean.
So if a particle can't be an individual, can't it still be a thing?
Finally, the words “particle” and “electron” are scientific terms. That must surely mean that if physicists say that “electrons are particles”, then electrons are particles. Full stop. Thus since the word “particle” is seen by both laypersons and scientists as a technical scientific term, then naturalist philosophers shouldn't encroach on the territory of physicists by questioning their usage.
2
Individuals and Modern
Logic
Ladyman and Ross stress the fact that modern logic (from Leibniz onward) has been fixated on “individual objects”. However, it may turn out that it's Ladyman and Ross who're fixated on individual objects.
In
modern logic (at its most basic) we have individual objects which are
symbolised by variables (such as x and y).
Those variables (of objects or things) are the subjects of
predication (or seen to be members of sets).
Ladyman
and Ross, on the other hand, see “logical
constants and variables as
being mere placeholders”
which are used for practical purposes. In other words, there are no
“ontological commitments” to the things/objects the variables
symbolise. Instead, the variables and constants are placeholders
which plot relations and structures.
So
it's fairly clear that quantum mechanics is on the minds of Ladyman
and Ross when they cite the limitations of modern logic. However,
modern logic wasn't designed to discuss quantum mechanics. Of course
it can now be said that (in theory) modern logic must also be
applicable to... well, everything. Therefore it must also be
applicable to the phenomena of quantum mechanics.
Mathematical
Structures and the Physical
That's a classic question of western metaphysics and it's been asked for over two thousand years. In both quantum mechanics and ontic structural realism, we're told that fields are fundamental, not particles. More precisely, particles in Quantum Field Theory (QFT) are seen as “excitations” of fields. Thus, to state the obvious, it's particles which are the excitations of fields, not fields which are the excitations of particles.
This makes fields fundamental. Or does it? Perhaps it's a difference which doesn't really make a difference – at least it doesn't to most hands-on physicists. (As the physicist John Polkinghorne once put it: “The average quantum mechanic is no more philosophical than the average motor mechanic.”)
Here
again we can question this fixation on what is and what isn't
fundamental. In certain respects, physics itself shows us that
particles/things aren't fundamental, despite the long history of attempts to find the fundamental entities of the world.
So
let's be specific about this. When Ladyman and Ross claim that
physics shows us that physical objects aren't spatially located,
aren't they only referring to particles? The same is
the case when they say that things
aren't “self-subsistent” (yet surely macro-objects aren't
self-subsistent either); they lack “primitive
indentity”; and that they aren't “ontologically fundamental”.
It's
troublesome to say that things
aren't “self-subsistent”. It's perhaps even more troublesome to
claim that relational structures are “ontologically subsistent”
and that relations are “primary to things”. At a prima face
level, this appears to be a Platonic position not on numbers or
mathematics, but on structures and relations. This isn't a surprise
if the structures and relations in physics are themselves
mathematical.
In
addition, Ladyman and Ross say that “things are nonexistent” or
that “things are dependent on
relational properties for their existence”. Thus can we also
argue that structure/relations are nonexistent or that
structure/relations are dependent on things for
their existence? In concrete terms, a pragmatist or
instrumentalist may say that whether or not one stresses fields or
particles depends on one's explanatory or experimental purposes.
So
not only can we ask Ladyman and Ross how abstract mathematical
structures relate to things/objects: we can also ask how they relate
to anything physical (or concrete). However, Ladyman and Ross
appear to reject these questions outright when they
write:
“The ‘world-structure’ just is and exists independently of us and we represent it mathematico-physically via our theories.... the fact that we only know the entities of physics in mathematical terms need not mean that they are actually mathematical entities.”
Here we need to know what's meant (philosophically meant) by the word “represent”. That is, what is the ontological (i.e., not representational) relation between structures and the “entities of physics”?
So it's helpful (if only in a limited sense) that Ladyman and Ross explicitly state that they aren't eliminativists about physical entities when they say that
“the fact that we only know the entities of physics in mathematical terms need not mean that they are actually mathematical entities”.
So how does that admission (if it is an admission) help us? Nothing is said about physical entities. Indeed Ladyman and Ross more or less say (in a Kantian manner) that nothing can be said about physical entities (i.e., other than what's said via the medium of mathematical structures). Perhaps, then, we should bite the bullet and accept this limitation if there's no way around it.
Yet
Ladyman and Ross are explicit about their Platonism
(or Pythagoreanism). Or, at the very least, their position is
Platonic/Pythagorean by default.
They
write:
“What makes the structure physical and not mathematical? That is a question that we refuse to answer. In our view, there is nothing more to be said about this that doesn't amount to empty words and venture beyond what the PNC allows. The 'world-structure' just is and exists independently of us and we represent it mathematico-physically via our theories.”
So whereas Platonists would be explicit and say it's all mathematics, Ladyman and Ross say that questions about their mathematical structuralism are “question[s] [they] refuse to answer”. Indeed they don't want to indulge in “empty words” in doing so. Ladyman and Ross are quite happy to express their Platonic and (structural) realist position by saying that the
“'world-structure' just is and [it] exists independently of us and we represent it mathematico-physically via our theories”.
Despite all that, the abstract and mathematical scheme of Ladyman and Ross does eventually give way to the physical (on concrete) when they say that the mathematical structures they endorse are “physically realized” and that the predicates they use are (as it were) attached to entities.
Thus this raises the question as to whether or not Ladyman and Ross are only realists about mathematical structures; or whether they're also realists about things - if via the route of mathematical structures. After all,
i) If Ladyman and Ross say that mathematical structures represent “real patterns”,
ii) then surely they can't also be saying saying that mathematical structures represent mathematical structures.
What's more:
i) If mathematical structure x represents a real pattern y,
ii) and this real pattern y represents a physical (or concrete) z,
iii) then mathematical structure x must also represent a physical (or concrete) z.
Structures: Syntax and Semantics
It's
of course structures which are meant to save the day when it comes to
both scientific realism and the well-known pessimistic
meta-induction. That is, structures are real and
they're passed on from (some) old scientific theories to (some) new
scientific theories. But here too there's a problem.
We can say that it's the mathematical syntax of scientific theories which is passed on - not their semantics. That is, we have a possible (or actual) structural continuity; though that only takes the form of mathematical equations.
We can say that it's the mathematical syntax of scientific theories which is passed on - not their semantics. That is, we have a possible (or actual) structural continuity; though that only takes the form of mathematical equations.
However,
doesn't syntax (at least in this case) require a semantics? In other
words, what is the subject matter of the syntax/mathematical
equations? If the subject matter is a Lockean
“something-I-know-not-what”,
then how can things we can't know be the subject matter of
equations (or of anything else for that matter)?
What's more, in physics the same equations can be mapped onto (or they can model) what are taken to be different physical phenomena. This is the inverse of the “underdetermination of theory by evidence”; in which the same evidence/observations (or the same physical phenomena) can give rise to different theories.
What's more, in physics the same equations can be mapped onto (or they can model) what are taken to be different physical phenomena. This is the inverse of the “underdetermination of theory by evidence”; in which the same evidence/observations (or the same physical phenomena) can give rise to different theories.
So
this shows us some disjunctions between abstract mathematical
structures and concrete physical phenomena. That is, the same
physical phenomenon can be mapped by different mathematical
structures; and the same mathematical structure can map different
physical phenomena. Perhaps this must mean that there's always a
remainder when it comes to any mapping of the concrete/physical by
abstract mathematical structures.
In
more relevant terms, in Quantum
Field Theory, different structures are used to map the same
spatiotemporal section of the physical world. Now it can also be
added that different structures must surely have different
ontologies. However, in practical term or in terms of prediction, it
can be said that any different ontologies of a spatiotemporal x
are differences which don't really make a difference.
(For
those who buy string theory, we have the examples of different
theories (such as type
1 and heterotic
SO(32)) which are mathematically equivalent. And even
in the case of Maxwell's equations for electricity and magnetism, if
one interchanges the electric fields for the magnetic fields and vice
versa, then the resulting equations are almost identical.)
Conclusion
It
would help if Ladyman and Ross explicitly stated that when they talk
of “things”, “objects” and “individuals”, what they have
in mind are the things, objects and individuals
which exist within the domain of quantum mechanics.
Indeed once that's acknowledged, the ontic structural realism of
Ladyman and Ross is far less radical than it appears at first sight.
Having said that, it's also true that Ladyman and Ross do sometimes
talk about things, objects and individuals at the “classical” or
macro-scale; though they
do so far less often. Not only that: what they do say about the
“classical world” will require supplementary arguments and data to
that which is used to justify their philosophical positions on
things, objects and individuals at the
quantum-mechanical level.
*****************************************
No comments:
Post a Comment