Lisa
Warenski is a naturalist. She's committed to the “scientific
method”. She characterizes that method by its “ongoing
responsiveness of theory to evidence”.
How
does the a priori fit into this?
Many
apriorists would argue that “some class of claims [are] immune to
empirical evidence”. Thus, such a position “would be in conflict
with the naturalist’s commitment to scientific method”.
Fallibilism
has been an important part of naturalist and empiricist philosophy - especially since C.S. Peirce. One would think that a naturalist and
fallibilist would be against the a priori in all its forms.
That isn't so in Warenski’s case. She says that
“[t]his
fallibilist notion of the a priori accords with the naturalist’s
commitment to scientific methodology in that it allows for
a priori-justified claims to be sensitive to further conceptual
developments and the expansion of evidence”.
Thus
not only is Warenski a fallibilist, she also applies her fallibilism
to the a priori itself; rather than simply rejecting it. She
says that
“[g]iven
the overthrow of Euclid’s parallel postulate and the discovery of
the set-theoretic paradoxes, an apriorist has reason to be
fallibilist about a priori claims independently of
considerations of naturalism”.
Warenski
divides her aprioristic fallibilism into two parts:
- One might allow that we could be mistaken in thinking that an a priori claim is true.
- One may be wrong in thinking that an a priori claim’s justification-conditions are actually a priori.
Warenski also accepts empirical defeasibility for a priori beliefs/claims. That empirical defeasibility applies to the two distinctions mentioned above:
- The ‘truth’ of an a priori statement/belief can be defeated on empirical grounds.
- The a priori warrant of a statement/belief can be defeated on empirical grounds.
There's
more to this.
An
a priori statement or belief can also be “revised on a
priori grounds”. Thus it would be a priori
defeasible rather than empirically defeasible. Warenski cites some
interesting examples of the a priori defeasibility of the a
priori. She says that
“[t]he
need to revise naive set theory was recognized on purely conceptual
grounds, and non-Euclidean geometries were developed prior to the
discovery that space was non-Euclidean, so arguably the grounds for
revision of an a priori claim could be purely conceptual”.
Thus
“conceptual revision” amounts to a priori revision,
according to Warenski. We can now say that “[i]f an a priori
claim were to be revised on purely conceptual grounds, the revision
would not undermine its a priori status”.
We
can revise the a priori with the a priori. Not only
that: a priori justified beliefs/claims may also come to be
empirically supported!... Though not so quick! If an a priori
justified belief/claim does come to be empirically supported, then
Warenski argues that we can conclude with two points:
- The belief/claim, or truth, wouldn't be defeated.
- The a priori justification of the belief/claim above would be defeated.
Warenski
offers us another interesting example. She writes:
“…
Gauss doubted the a priori
status of Euclid’s parallel postulate, understood as a claim about
physical space; however, he thought it to be empirically
corroborated.”
Here
again there are two things to conclude from the quote above:
- The parallel postulate itself wasn't undermined.
- The a priori warrant for the parallel postulate was undermined.
A Priori Fallibilism & Naturalism
Despite
this fusion of naturalism and apriorism (if that’s what it really
is), Warenski happily accepts that a naturalist account of the a
priori will prove to be, at best, problematic. She gives two
primary reasons for this:
- “The range of different kinds of beliefs, inference rules or claims that we might classify as a priori may not admit of a single positive characterization.”
- “Different standards apply to different forms of positive epistemic appraisal: the conditions that must be met for entitlement or epistemically-blameless reasoning are weaker than what must be met for justification sufficient for knowledge.”
It's still clear that Warenski’s principle target isn't radical rationalism; but (extreme?) Quinean naturalism. Putting her case intuitively, she says that
“[i]t
is hard to think of convincing cases of empirical observations that
should count as evidence against elementary principles such as the
law of identity or modus ponens”.
However,
the rationalist shouldn't think that Warenski is a completely
compliant rationalist.For
example, she says that “given the peculiarities of quantum
mechanics, perhaps there are such possible observations”.
A
Priori Fallibilism & Revisability
Warenski
is more explicit about apriorist fallibilism. She says that
“[a]
fallibilist about a priori
justification thinks that an a priori
claim is empirically indefeasible, but he allows that we don’t know
that future conceptual developments will never come to reveal
empirical evidence against it”.
That
characterization may sound self-contradictory at first sight. She's
saying that a priori claim is indefeasible as it stands today;
though it may defeasible according to how things stands in the
future.
This
isn't unlike Rudolph Carnap’s position on analyticity. Thus we can
distinguish the following alternatives:
- An analytic statement. Full stop.
- Analytic-in-L
And in the case of fallibilist apriorism:
- An a priori belief or justification. Full stop.
- An a priori belief or justification at time t. (Or, perhaps, a priori-in-L.)
Warenski’s
is clearly aware of one possible riposte to her position:
- If P is known to be true,
- then P is true.
- If P is known to be true,
- then it follows that P won't come to be undermined.
- Therefore the fallibilist can't claim that both P is known to be true and that it's not known that P won't come to be undermined in the future.
If
the a priori is revisable. Then logic, after all, is
revisable. And then we're back to Quine.
Reference
Warenski,
Lisa. (2008) ‘Naturalism,
Fallibilism, and the A Priori’
No comments:
Post a Comment