Saturday 26 February 2022

Philip Goff on the “Brute” Identity Theory: Flogging a Dead Horse?

Philosopher Philip Goff tells us that “science is supposed to offer explanations [of the] subjective inner world of feeling and experience”. Does it?

The English philosopher and panpsychist Philip Goff offers us a broad dismissal of what he calls the “brute identity theory”. In Goff’s own words:

“The brute identity theory is very unsatisfying. Science is supposed to offer explanations I want to know how processes in the brain result in a subjective inner world of feeling and experience.”

It must be said here that Philip Goff is almost entirely beholden to the prior arguments and positions of the philosophers Saul Kripke (1940 — ) and David Chalmers (1966 — ). These two philosophers attacked identity theorists with the argument that they can’t — or couldn’t — identify (to use Goff’s own examples) feelings, experiences and pains with brain states (or, indeed, with anything physical). And that’s because human subjects are (as it’s often put) “directly aware” of the “qualitative” nature of their feelings, experiences and pains. That is, all these things have qualitative features (or properties) which no brain state ever has.

Explanations?

Firstly, science (if we can speak of science in the singular) does “offer explanations” of the “subjective inner world of feeling and experience”. It’s just that none of its explanations satisfy Philip Goff.

More relevantly, explanations as to how “processes in the brain result in a subjective inner world of feeling and experience” were even provided by the old-school identity theorists of the 1950s and 1960s. (Why is Goff going back so far? See the history here.) And neuroscientists and others today also provide explanations on this subject. It’s just — again — that Goff doesn’t like any of their explanations. That’s because Goff believes that all such explanations lack something — they lack a certain je ne sais quoi. And Goff’s je ne sais quoi is particularly philosophical.

What’s more, the (as it were) how-explanation which Goff demands may never be forthcoming. (David Chalmers asks “why”, not “how” — see here.) That may well be because it’s a demand which can never be met — not even in principle. (Remember Goff’s words “[s]cience is supposed to offer explanations” here.)

Think about this.

Would — or could — any physical how-explanation of what Goff calls the “subjective inner world” ever satisfy him? That is, would — or could — any move from the brain to the inner world of “feeling and experience” ever satisfy Goff? After all, if Goff believes — from the very start! — that feelings and experiences are both definitionally and metaphysically different to anything at the level of the brain, then literally all the how-explanations which lead from the brain to feelings and experiences will always be automatically ruled out. In other words, Goff demands an “explanation” which can never be given — at least not if given on his own impossible terms… And I use the word “impossible” because even a (careful) physicalist like the Korean-American philosopher Jaegwon Kim (1934–2019) had this to say on a closely- related matter:

[I]f we think of certain properties as having their own intrinsic characterizations that are entirely independent of anther set of properties, there is no hope of reducing the former to the latter.”

In any case, Goff (at least partly) came to the conclusions stated above by analysing the claims and positions of the identity theorists of the 1950s and 1960s. (Goff doesn’t mention this historical detail.)

The Identity Theory

Let me quote Philip Goff in full:

“If we have sufficient empirical evidence that pain is identical with brain state X, which brute identity theorists claim we would have if pain were found to be systematically correlated with brain state X, then we can simply assert the identity and the case is closed. It is a philosophical confusion, according to the brute identity theory, to suppose that anything more is required.”

And, elsewhere, Goff puts the words “[f]eelings are no more real than the Loch Ness Monster” into the mouth of a Dr. Ivor Cutler; who’s a fictional neuroscientist — and presumably an Identity Theorist — at the factual California Institute of Technology.

Firstly, according to Goff’s take on identity theorists, there’s a too-smooth move from the fact that

pain Y is “systematically correlated with brain state X

to the conclusion that

“we can [therefore] simply assert the identity and the case is closed”.

Yet it’s not that brain state X and pain state Y are systematically correlated which automatically leads to an identity. It’s that this systematic correlation gives the identity theorist a very strong reason to believe that there is — in fact — an identity. (The difference between type and token identity will be ignored here; as well as the fact that even if the identity theory were correct, a particular pain may still not — or even will not — be identical to a particular place in the brain.)

The following is how the American experimental psychologist Edwin Boring (as quoted by U.T. Placeput it in the 1930s:

“To the author a perfect correlation is identity. Two events that always occur together at the same time in the same place, without any temporal or spatial differentiation at all, are not two events but the same event. The mind-body correlations as formulated at present, do not admit of spatial correlation, so they reduce to matters of simple correlation in time. The need for identification is no less urgent in this case.”

And the following is how Valerie Gray Hardcastle went on to put it some 60 years after Boring:

[I]f you find structural isomorphisms between our perceptions and twitches in the brain, then that is taken to be a good reason to think that the mind is nothing more than activity in the brain. (What other sort of evidence could you use?)”

Of course it’s the case that not all correlations entail — or even imply — identities. It’s just that in some cases they do.

So, clearly, smoking lots of cigarettes came to be strongly correlated with lung cancer. However, smoking lots of cigarettes is still not (to state the obvious) identical to lung cancer.

As already stated, Philip Goff essentially tackles the positions of the identity theorists of the 1950s and 1960s. Yet I doubt that any identity theorist — even at this stage in philosophical history — ever denied that there’s a first-person (or “inner”) angle to the physical-mental identities they posited.

The View From the Inside

Perhaps the seemingly(?) non-physical nature of Goff’s “feeling and experience” is largely — or even entirely — down to people’s subjective (or first-person) take on them. That is, to the (as it were) “owners” of feelings and experiences, such things do indeed seem to be non-physical. Yet do feelings and experiences seeming-to-be-non-physical mean that they are non-physical? Perhaps there’s a fundamental reason (purely phenomenological in nature) as to why the owner (or haver) of experience or feeling C takes it to be non-physical.

All this all ties in with broader takes on the privacy of feelings and experiences.

So why is fundamental privacy given so much credence in this philosophical debate?

Firstly, how do we move from that stress on the view-from-the-inside (in this particular case, the non-physical nature of feelings and experiences) to anything outside that inner domain? How do we move to anything specifically scientific — and indeed anything philosophical — from that which is deemed to be intrinsically private? In other words, what work is this innerness doing? Is it just a brute or fundamental fact — full stop?

The following argument is how the British-American philosopher Peter Carruthers (1952- ) expresses the relevance of privacy to this debate. He writes:

(1) Conscious states are private to the person who has them.

(2) Brain-states are not private: like any other physical state, they form part of the public realm.

(Conclusion) So (by Leibniz’s Law) conscious states are not in fact identical with brain-states.”

Not many people would doubt premise (1) above. What’s more, a behaviourist or eliminativist position isn’t being advanced here either. However, this question remains:

What can we conclude given that feelings and experiences are inner or private?

More clearly:

Is the claim that feelings and experiences are are non-physical itself largely (or even entirely) down to their being (as it were) viewed from the inside?

This means that it follows that because “[c]onscious states are private to the person who has them”, then the notion of the non-physicality of those states will be private to the person who has them too. Yet how can we draw out the actual non-physicality of (in Goff’s case) feelings and experiences from such personal “reports” on them?

Again, from a private (or phenomenological) viewpoint, feelings and experiences do seem to be non-physical. Yet that private seeming doesn’t mean that feelings and experiences are non-physical. Perhaps that seeming-to-be-non-physical is largely a product of personal psychology, learning, culture, history and sociology.

To repeat.

When a subject has a feeling or experience, it seems (to that subject) to be non-physical. Yet why should we accept that feeling or experience C is non-physical simply because its owner takes it to be that way? What relevance does that personal (or private) account of a feeling or experience have on its actual metaphysical status?

To take an extreme analogy.

To subject S, the cricket bat in the water seems to be bent. Yet that doesn’t mean that the cricket bat in the water is bent — it’s refracted. Similarly, subject S hallucinating a red goblin is “private to the person” who has that hallucination. Yet we wouldn’t conclude that the red goblin exists.

Now take another loosely analogical argument.

The reader’s experience (or observation) of a specific concrete building isn’t identical to that concrete building itself. And my own experience (or observation) of that concrete building isn’t identical to the reader’s experience (or observation) of that very same concrete building. In these simple cases, then, few people would claim an absolute identity between an experience (or observation) of a concrete building (or an experience/observation of anything else) and the building itself. That is, the experiences (or observations) of that building are never confused (or conflated) with the building itself (unless, that is, one is an out-and-out idealist).

Yet aren’t many people doing something similar to that when it comes to their own feelings and experiences?

Again, feelings and experiences seem to be non-physical. Therefore many people believe that feelings and experiences are non-physical. Yet that would be like seeing the concrete building as actually being black and white when wearing sunglasses (or even if one is suffering from a retinal problem of vision). Sure, the cases aren’t identical because feelings and experiences are private or inner; whereas the concrete building is far from being private. Yet that doesn’t mean that we can’t make mistakes about private conscious (or mental) states. Indeed there’s a large literature on this very subject which tells us that we often do (see here).

So perhaps we can conclude that the seemingly non-physical nature of feelings and experiences is purely a product of private states or describing things from the inside. As Carruthers (again) puts it:

“Even if descriptions of consciousness experiences are logically independent of all descriptions of physical states (as the cartesian conception implies) it may in fact be the case that those descriptions are descriptions of the very same things. This is just what the thesis of mind/brain identity affirms.”

Thus we shouldn’t also conclude that such feelings and experiences actually are non-physical from our descriptions.

In addition, does this mean that such people are taking their own positions — or descriptions — on the (metaphysical) nature of their own feelings and experiences to be gospel?

That last claim doesn’t mean that people make mistakes about the very (as it were) having of a feeling or experience or even about its phenomenology. The mistakes come only when people describe — or theorise about — their feelings and experiences. Mistakes also come about because of people’s assumptions about their own feelings and experiences. (The non-physical nature of feelings and experiences isn’t the only example of this.) Thus such descriptions, theories and assumptions may be highly mistaken or confused.

All that said, there’s no eliminativist or behaviourist denial of feelings and experiences here. What is being questioned is what people say or believe about their own feelings and experiences. And, in this case at least, many people believe (if only when pressed by philosophers and given a philosophical vocabulary) that all their feelings and experiences are non-physical.

Yet despite all the above, mental privacy can be — or at least it can become — scientifically kosher.

Paul Churchland on the Introspection of Neural States

So let’s finally consider the Canadian philosopher Paul Churchland (1942 — ) position on the introspection of mental states.

Despite what some (or even many) philosophers and laypeople believe, Churchland doesn’t deny that there’s such a thing as introspection. (For that matter, Churchland doesn’t deny that people have thoughts, pains or mental states generally.) That said, his position on introspection — and on much else — is truly radical.

For example, take Churchland’s detail as to why even introspection deals with scientifically-acceptable phenomena.

To begin with, Churchland states the following:

“For if mental states are indeed brain states, then it is really brain states we have been introspecting all along, though without fully appreciating what they are.”

So when we introspect we “may discriminate efficiently between a great variety of neural states”. However, we may not “being able to reveal on its own the detailed nature of the states being discriminated”.

The conclusion here is that although Churchland wants to eliminate propositional attitudes (see here) such as beliefs, desires, etc. (as basically seen as being “sentences in the brain”), he doesn’t actually want to eliminate mental states such as feelings and experiences (see here) in toto. Quite simply, that’s because this would be virtually impossible today or even in the future. Instead Churchland wants to re-envision what mental states are and how we should theorise (or philosophise) about them.

Conclusion

The last two sections directly above were partly counterpoised against Thomas Nagel’s very-well-known and much-discussed paper ‘What is it like to be a bat?’ (1974). Arguably, it can be said that the very essence of this paper isn’t the non-physicality or irreducibility of “qualia” or the impossibility of “knowing what it’s like to be a bat”: it is the prime importance of human subjectivity or the human first-person perspective. (Of course all these issues are strongly related to each other.)

As Nagel himself puts it in that paper:

[E]very subjective phenomenon is essentially connected with a single point of view, and it seems inevitable that an objective, physical theory will abandon that point of view.”

Nagel also says that “one must take up the bat’s point of view” and that

[i]t is difficult to understand what could be meant by the objective character of an experience, apart from the particular point of view from which its subject apprehends it”.

Yet in the above a position was advanced which was roughly similar to John Heil’s in that there was no denial of the inner there. In Heil’s own words:

“Attempts to accommodate subjectivity to the ‘third-person perspective’ are bound to fail. We must recognise ‘subjectivity as a rock-bottom element’ of reality and find a way of reconciling subjectivity with the ‘third-person perspective’ in a way that leaves subjectivity intact.’”

Finally: the (to quote Nagel again) “single point of view” isn’t denied: it’s what we make of it that matters.

[I can be found on Twitter here.]








No comments:

Post a Comment