Strongly
connected to Nancy
Cartwright’s
capacity-ascription
account
of science (or physics), as well as her counterfactual
analysis
of singular
causal claims,
is her rejection of the “unity
of
science”
hypothesis as first strongly suggested by Otto Neurath.
One can see how the disunity of science may follow from Cartwright’s
rejection of modal
and universal generalisations and the particularity of singular
causal claims:
She
writes:
"Now,
it’s not that I know that nature is disunified, but I wouldn’t
think it was very sensible to build an entire scientific methodology
on an assumption that it must be unified. And if it’s not unified,
in certain specific ways, then certain specific methodological
assumptions that we make in doing science are mistaken, and they’re
going to be costly and lead to mistakes, and I don’t want us to
make methodological mistakes based on a kind of Holy Grail
metaphysics."
It’s
not that Cartwright has proved/demonstrated that nature is disunified
either: it’s just that no one has proved – or could prove –
that it's unified. That means that it could indeed be disunified. And
if it is in fact disunified, then
"certain
specific methodological assumptions that we make in doing science are
mistaken, and they’re going to be costly and lead to mistakes".
Perhaps
it would be better, then, to simply assume the disunification of
nature for methodological reasons in that even if we've no conclusive
evidence that nature is disunified today, that evidence may well be
forthcoming in the future. Indeed wouldn’t it be easier to falsify
the
unity of science (or nature) hypothesis than to falsify the disunity
of science or nature hypothesis? After all, one concrete example of
nature’s disunity would falsify the assumption that nature is in
fact unified. (Though, in a Quinian
response
to Karl
Popper:
holistically, no single observation - or test - can ever falsify a
very broad scientific theory.) Whereas no matter how much evidence we
may have for nature’s essential unity, it's always possible that
some time in the future we'll discover something which basically
falsifies the unity of nature (or science) hypothesis.
This
too is basically a Humean
(not Popperian) point.
As
Cartwright argues about the obsession with universal
generalisations
and the modal-property applications which are supposed to be
applicable to nature, they're nothing but a “metaphysical
pipedream”. So Cartwright now argues that the belief in the unity
of science (or the unity of nature) is "based on a kind of Holy
Grail metaphysics". Just as modal universal generalisations
bring order and simplicity to the multiplicities and the complexity,
so the assumption of nature’s essential unity brings order and
simplicity out of multiplicity and complexity. In fact the order and
simplicity of universal generalisations go along with the order and
simplicity that's assumed by the unity of nature (or science)
hypothesis.
Cartwright
gives her own reasons why she thinks that scientists (or should I say
certain philosophers of science?) feel a strong need for a scientific
methodology that's certain, content-less and applicable across the
board of all sciences. She
writes:
"[A]nd now we move on to the new conclusion that there’s no
methodology which is certain and has any meat to it, any real
ramifications, other than ‘think carefully’ or something like
that, which doesn’t really tell you what to do, how do we ensure
that we have objective knowledge?"
It's
almost as if – or literally is - the case that scientists (or
philosophers of science) view scientific methodologies as logicians
view the rules of inference, argument-forms or other forms of
deductive validity. That is, just as correct rules of inference
secure truth (or just correctness) for the logician, so methodologies
(or even a single methodology) will secure science both truth and
objectivity - if not also certainty. But this isn't logic and
scientific methodologies are never purely logical in nature. Quite
simply this is because they have content.
Logic is primarily about form. That is, if science is largely about
evidence or even truth, then logic is largely about correctness and
the forms of logical reasoning or inference. Even the
hypothetico-deductive
model isn't
a case of pure logic being applied to the domain of science. Clearly,
the only logical part of the hypothetico-deductive model of science
is the deductive
part. And even that isn't purely logical in nature because the
contingency of the hypotheses used, and from which we deduce
scientific theorems, will pass on their contingency (or lack of
necessity) to those theorems regardless of the validity of the
deductive
inferences
which are correctly adhered to.
However,
it can be doubted that any scientist - and certainly very few
philosophers of science - would accept a methodology which simply
said “think carefully”, “don’t generalise too hastily” or
whatever. What they actually want is something with a lot of “meat
to it”. Something which will “ensure that we have objective
knowledge”. Of course a philosopher of science like Paul
Feyerabend (amongst
others) wouldn't even want a scientific methodology which “really
[told] you what to do”. Why would anyone scientist (or any one
else) want that? It would destroy scientific invention and
creativity. And creativity and invention (as scientists themselves
tell us) are is essential to much science – and not just to
theoretical scientific research.
Cartwright
herself gives an example of her anti-methodology approach being taken
as an attack on scientific
objectivity
- or
at least a threat to it. In her case it's her scepticism (if that’s
the right word) about the use of probability in science. She
writes:
"And
my attacks, for instance, on being able to use probability as a
sure-fire way to infer causes, have come to be seen as an attack on
objectivity,
though
I’m not at all sure that’s right."
Is
the use of probability itself a scientific methodology? Or is it
something which can be used within
a methodology? It's strange, then, that given the nature of
probability
theory (that
it deals with probabilities, not certainties), that the scientific
objectivists (for want of a better term) require that probability
gives them “a sure-fire way to infer causes”.
Probability theory can never give you a sure-fire way to do anything.
In
addition, I’m not sure about this example of “backwards
causation”.
Do we “infer causes” in science at all? Don’t we primarily
infer (or predict) effects? Perhaps in science we do both. After all,
if we chance upon a blackened and smoking forest, we can infer the
cause – that there's been a fire of some kind. Similarly, if we
chance upon a forest fire, we can infer (or predict) that the forest
will soon be blackened and full of smoke. So causal explanation works
both from causes to effects and from effects to causes. Is either one
or the other of primary importance in science? Perhaps they both are.
Finally,
I’m not even sure how an attack on the fallibility of probability
theory is an attack
on objectivity in
the first place. Is it simply because probability theory doesn't give
the scientist
certainty?
In what way is the word ‘objectivity’ being used here? Without an
explanation of what precisely the scientific objectivists (or the
objectivist philosophers of science) want with their objectivity,
it's hard to make sense of what they say (or what Cartwright) is
saying here.
No comments:
Post a Comment