i) Introduction
ii) Graham Priest on Nothing as an Object
iii) Quantifying Nothing
iv) Russell & Quine
Rhetorically speaking, can mere words bring objects into existence?
As
we've seen, Martin
Heidegger
was perplexed by the fact that we can refer to nothing.
He
asked,
“What about this nothing?” Heidegger
also
asked:
“The
nothing – what else can it be for science but an outrage and a
phantasm?”
Heidegger
contended
that
“[s]cience
wants to know nothing of the nothing”.
According
to Heidegger (who was critical of science for many other reasons
too), science's main sin is that
it
“tries
to express its proper essence it calls upon the nothing for help”.
(Note the words “the nothing”.) That is, science refer to (the)
nothing
(or at least scientists use the word “nothing”), yet it “rejects”
nothing.
(One wonders why Heidegger singled out science in this respect. After
all, all of us use the word “nothing” and refer to nothing.)
More specifically:
i)
Do we “posit [nothing's] being” when we refer to nothing?
ii)
Or do we
simply use the word “nothing” because it's useful in certain - even many - contexts?
What
did Heidegger think?
This:
“With
regard to the nothing, question and answer alike are absurd.”
Graham
Priest on Nothing
as an Object
Graham
Priest
too
appears to believe (if only when viewed critically) that language
creates objects.
Actually, he doesn't actually make that rhetorical claim. (The words
are mine.) Instead, his actual words can result in this
interpretation.
In
Priest's
own
words:
“An
object is anything you can refer to with a noun phrase, think about
quantify over.”
Thus, this is a liberal (or pluralist) position on objects in that Priest
concludes
that
“so
there are many objects, like Marcus, like Bond, like the City
University of New York, like the Sun and so on all these things you
can think about you can refer to”.
Indeed, this is a positively Meinongian
conclusion. (That is, apart from the fact that Alexius
Meinong
never
stressed – and possibly even ignored – language.) However, as
Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Rudolf Carnap and many others
have put it (in their various ways), Priest and Heidegger might well
have been “misled
by language”.
Quantifying
Nothing
We
must add here that apart from language, Priest also emphasises
quantification.
However, this amounts to a very similar thing – quantification too
brings
objects into existence.
(The miraculous powers of the “backward
E”
– as Hilary
Putnam
put it.)
Priest
refers to quantifying over both everything
and nothing.
However, he has a position on quantification that's at odds with the
common one. Usually, it's thought that all acts of quantification have
a specific domain in mind. Priest, on the other hand, believes
that “it's
okay to use a quantifier with the widest
possible scope”.
That is, it's fine to quantify over literally everything.
(Like
Russell's
universal
set?)
Priest
offers us a variation on the theme discussed in the history of
philosophy (see later) by arguing for the following:
i)
If we “quantify over” any given x,
ii)
then x must be an
“object” of some kind.
According
to Priest, we also refer to (or quantify over) everything
– so that
too must be an object. Yes, Priest says that “everything is an
object”, just like nothing.
(It's then that Priest gets all dialethic by saying that “it's not
an object” too. But we'll leave that until later.) That is, Priest
applies the same logic to everything
as he does to nothing.
The
following words will
make that clear:
“Everything
is the mereological sum of every object [] If everything is the
fusion of the sum of all objects, [then] what is nothingness?
Nothingness is the sum of everything that isn't an object because
everything is an object. [Nothingness is] the sum of no things. What
you get when you fuse together no things is exactly nothingness.”
Philosophers
too have referred to nothing,
and hence it must be an object. Priest
himself refers to Ludwig
Wittgenstein
and Nagarjuna.
He says
that
these two
thinkers
“tell[]
you that something is ineffable; and then [they] explain why it's
ineffable - thereby talking about”.
That
is certainly the case with the Tractatus,
in which Wittgenstein
discusses the “form
of the world”.
We also had Kant's
endless references to noumena; and that's even though he believed that nothing
could be known
about them. Then again, all this is also true of the round
square
or the brick
with a sense of humour
- which I've just referred to!
To
repeat. Priest goes all linguistic (not all ontological – which
doesn't mean there's an absolute distinction) when he says
that
“'nothing’,
can also be a noun
phrase”.
Basically, that's because we can and do talk
about it. Or, more specifically, Hegel and Heidegger talked about it a lot.
That
is,
“[w]e
may say that Hegel and Heidegger both wrote about nothing”.
Moreover,
“nothing” is “not [always] a quantifier phrase”. That is,
it's not all about counting or quantifying. It's also about a thing
– an object.
One
other way in which we can talk about nothing
is to note that “[w]e can say that [Hegel and Heidegger] said
different things about it”. In addition, Christianity talks about
nothing
in that the “Abrahamic God is supposed to have created the world”
out of nothing.
We
can see that Priest is fully committed to Plato's
Beard
in that human sayings
bring things into existence.
So
now let's do some history of philosophy.
Russell
and Quine
Bertrand
Russell - in his 1918 paper 'Existence
and Description'
- believed that in order for names
to be names,
they must name – or refer to - things which exist. Take this
remarkable
passage:
“The
fact that you can discuss the proposition 'God exists' is a proof
that 'God', as used in that proposition, is a description not a name.
If 'God' were a name, no question as to existence could arise.”
That,
clearly, is fairly similar to Parmenides's
own position
on the use of the word “nothing”. Russell's actual argument, however, is
very different.
[Personally,
I don't have much time for Russell's argument. It seems to have the
character of a stipulation [That is, names
must name existing things.].
It's primary purpose is logical and philosophical. Russell, at the
time, was reacting to the “ontological
slums”
- as Quine put it - of Alexius
Meinong.
However, this semantic philosophy simply seems like a stipulation -
or a normative position - designed to solve various philosophical
problems.]
As
for Quine,
he had no problem with the naming
of nonbeings
or non-existents (though non-being
and non-existence
aren't the same thing). In his 1948 paper, 'On
What There Is',
he firstly dismisses Russell's position. Quine, however, puts
Russell's position in the mouth of McX and uses the word “Pegasus”
rather than the word “God”.
“He
confused the alleged named object Pegasus with the meaning of the
word 'Pegasus', therefore concluding that Pegasus must be in order
that the word have meaning.”
Put
simply, a name can have a “meaning” without it having to refer to
something which exists (or even having to refer to something which
has being).
Quine unties meaning from reference, whereas Russell only thought in
terms of reference (or, at the least, he strongly tied meaning to
reference).
Parmenides
made a similar mistake.
The
ancient Greek philosopher didn't think that a name could have a
meaning without the thing
being named also existing or (having) being. However, we can speak of
a something
(an x)
that doesn't exist because the naming of such an x
doesn't entail or even imply its existence. However, and in homage to
Meinong (as well as, perhaps, to the philosopher David
Lewis), philosophers can now ask us the following question:
What
kind of being does the named object (or thing) have?
If
we return to Russell. His theory is an attempt to solve that problem
by arguing that if a named x
doesn't exist (or have being), then that name must be a “disguised
description”.
(In the case of the name “Pegasus”, the description would be “the
fictional horse which has such and
such characteristics”.)
Note:
1)
Some of the quoted words and passages from Graham Priest in the above
are taken from the 'Everything
and Nothing'
seminar – a Robert Curtius Lecture of Excellence at Bonn University
- which Priest gave. I relied on both the transcript and the video
itself. However, I've edited a lot of what Priest says in that
seminar to make it more comprehensible. For example, I removed many
of the uses of the word “so”, added full stops, commas and
suchlike. Hopefully, the philosophical content is kept intact. None
of this applicable to the words and passages I quote which come from
Priest's papers and books.
To
follow: 'Graham Priest, Martin Heidegger, Dialetheism and Nothing
(3)'.
No comments:
Post a Comment