i) Nothing
Both is and is Not an Object
ii) Ontologically Dependent on Nothing
iii) Possible
Worlds and Dialetheism
iv) Is
Dialetheism About Reality?
iv) Quantum
Mechanics
**********************
One
can stress the ontological nature of his dialetheism
in that it has been claimed that isn't a formal
logic.
Instead, it's argued to be "a
thesis about truth".
Thus it's no surprise that Graham
Priest
ties it to nothing
and therefore to ontology.
Nothing
Both
is and is Not an Object
Graham
Priest
hints
at dialetheism in
this
passage:
“Nothing
is not an object because you've taken away all objects to get it.”
Elsewhere,
Priest says that nothing is
an object. Thus nothing “both is and is not” an object. Hence the
dialetheism.
So
despite the work of Russell, Quine, Carnap, etc., Priest
comes
out with phrases such
as
“we
posit nothingness
in advance as something that is such-and-such we posit it as a being
a thing”.
No;
we don't “posit” anything ontological when we use the word
“nothing”. Some philosophers (very few) have done so; although
“we”, generally, haven't.
Priest
then offers us the contradiction.
The
first
horn
of the contradiction is that “nothingness is not an object”. The
second horn is that nothingness “is an object”. Dialetheists (or
at least Priest) make sense of this by arguing that nothingness
“depends like all objects on nothingness”. The argument is this:
i)
All objects depend on nothingness.
ii)
So if nothingness is
an object,
iii)
then it too must depend on nothingness.
iv)
Therefore nothingness
must depend on itself.
Priest
poetically calls this “going
from nothingness
to nothingness”.
Then
we get back to the other dialetheic horn – nothing
is not
an
object. That is:
i)
“Only objects depend on nothing/ness.”
ii)
If nothing/ness is not an object,
iii)
Then it doesn't depend on nothingness. (It doesn't depend on itself.)
Or
in Priest's own
words:
“[N]othing
depends on itself. Though since it's not an object, it doesn't depend
on itself.”
Here
again we have a contradiction.
Or
so the argument goes.
If
Priest firstly accepts that “nothingness is an object”, then
these contradictions are bound to follow. In other words, if we begin
with the claim that nothingness
is an object,
then no wonder Priest can then say
that
“nothing
[] depends on itself; but since it's not an object, it doesn't depend
on itself”.
Yes,
that is indeed a statement of a contradiction. But do we have the
reality of a contradiction?
(Readers
will need to backtrack to the section
on objects
in order to see exactly why Priest believes that nothingness can be
seen as an object.)
Here's
some more dialetheism from Priest. He
says:
“Since
[nothing] is an object, it is something.
But it is the absence of all things too; so nothing is nothing. It is
no thing, no object. Here, Heidegger got it exactly right: What is
the nothing?”
Then,
in a note, Priest is more dialetheically explicit when he
states
the following:
“Nothing,
then, is a most strange, contradictory, thing. It both is and is not
an object; it both is and is not something.”
So
Priest appears to be magicking dialetheisms (as it were) out of the
air. Actually, he doesn't accept that all the contradictions he
mentions (in various places) are real contradictions (i.e., he denies
that logical “explosion”
also
applies
to dialetheism).
For
example, Priest
rejects
the posited contradiction found in Wittgenstein's Tractatus
idea that the
“form
of the world”
is ineffable. Why? Basically, because we can both speak about - and
describe - it. On the other hand, Priest does seem to accept that
“the ground of reality [] embodies another contradiction” because
nothingness “both grounds itself and doesn't ground itself” and
“it is and isn't an object”. There nothingness is “the
contradictory ground of reality”.
Ontologically Dependent on Nothing
Priest
then makes
this
massive claim:
“At
the ground of reality you have nothing - this contradictory ground of
nothingness. So at the ground of reality there is one enormous
contradiction.”
Firstly,
why is nothing
a “ground”? Indeed what is it for “nothing to be the ground of
reality”? And where, exactly, is the “contradiction”?
No
wonder Priest then says that this “is
good old-fashioned
metaphysics”. (It is!) And it's no surprise, either, that Priest
also ask: “What
to
make of the contradictory ground of reality?” And he concludes:
“I'm
going to leave [that question] to theologians to make sense of that
question.”
So
why theologians and not philosophers?
Possible
Worlds and Dialetheism
Priest
uses possible-worlds
speak to justify his dialetheism. Take
this
example:
“It
might be thought that the fact that ¬(A
∧ ¬A) holds at a
world entails that one or other A
and ¬A fails; but
this does not necessarily follow.”
Is
Priest saying that ¬(A
∧ ¬A)
holds at the actual world (i.e., our world); though not “necessarily”
at all possible worlds? Or does Priest believe that only at other
possible worlds A
∧ ¬A
holds?
In any case, the dialetheic position is that A
∧ ¬A
is not necessarily
false.
Priest
offers us the following symbolisation of his position:
¬A
is true at w iff is A
false at w.
¬A
is false at w iff A is
true at w.
So
what about Priest's
A ∧
¬A?
According
to Priest, “it is possible for A
to be both true and false at a world”. That is, of course, the
dialetheic position. Yet does this position require possible-worlds
theory when Priest (elsewhere) has said that it's also applicable at
our world – the actual
world?
Not
surprisingly, Priest concedes
that
“it
is natural to ask whether there really are possible worlds at which
something may be both true and false”.
He
also believes that this is a “fair question”. Nonetheless, Priest
also argues that
“the
best reasons for thinking this to be possible are also reasons for
thinking it to be actual”.
That
seems to follow from the earlier possible-worlds logic. We can now
argue
the following:
i)
If it's possible for A
∧ ¬A to be true at
at least one possible world,
ii)
then it's also likely to be - or possibly - true at our actual world.
Is
Dialetheism About Reality?
In
order to tackle Priest's later dialetheic views on quantum mechanics
(see the next section), let's firstly take the words of Bryson Brown
as an introduction.
Bryson
Brown
(in his paper
'On Paraconsistency')
stresses
“the world”,
rather
than
words.
That is, he's stresses ontology, not semantics.
More
specifically, Bryson stresses the importance of inconsistency
for
dialetheism. He also says that dialetheists are “radical
paraconsistentists”.
He
writes:
“[Dialetheists] hold that the world is inconsistent, and
aim at a general logic that goes beyond all the consistency
constraints of classical logic.”
Deriving
the notion of an inconsistent
world
(or a world which contains contradictions) from our psychological
and/or epistemological limitations (as well as from accepted notions
in the philosophy of science and mathematics) is problematic. In
other words, the epistemological position that we have inconsistent
(or even contradictory) positions/systems can't also be applied to
the world itself.
Another
way to put this is in terms of set-theoretic
paradoxes,
as also mentioned by Bryson Brown.
Brown
says that
“the
dialetheists take paradoxes
such as the
liar
and the paradoxes of naïve set theory at face value”. That is, it
may be the case that dialetheists choose - for logical and/or
philosophical reasons - to accept paradoxes even though they also
believe that, ultimately, they aren't true of the actual world. Then
again, Brown continues
by saying
that dialetheists “view
these paradoxes as proofs that certain inconsistencies are true”.
Thus:
These inconsistencies are true of what?
True
only of the paradoxes (in themselves, as it were)?
Or
true of the world itself?
Again,
this stress on the world may betray a naïve, crude and, perhaps, an
old-fashioned view of logic. Nonetheless, Priest himself does mention
“reality” on a few occasions. When discussing the virtue of
simplicity,
for example, he asks the following
question:
“If
there is some reason for supposing that reality is, quite generally,
very consistent – say some sort of transcendental argument – then
inconsistency is clearly a negative criterion. If not, then perhaps
not.”
This
again concerns reality.
As it is, it's difficult to see how the world can be either
inconsistent or consistent. This position is similar – or parallel
– to
Baruch Spinoza's
philosophical point that the world can only, well, be.
(Graham Priest is a Buddhist.) Thus:
“I
would warn you that I do not attribute to nature either beauty or
deformity, order or confusion. Only in relation to our imagination
can things be called beautiful or ugly, well-ordered or confused.”
What
we say
about the world (whether in science, philosophy, mathematics, logic
or everyday life) may well be consistent or inconsistent. However,
the world itself
can neither be consistent nor inconsistent. Thus, it seems to follow,
that inconsistency is neither a “negative criterion” nor a
positive
criterion.
Quantum
Mechanics
Priest
says
that
“those
who worked on early quantum mechanical models of the atom regarded
the [Neils] Bohr theory [as] certainly inconsistent”.
Priest
then tells us:
“[Y]et
its empirical predictions were spectacularly successful.”
Priest
appears to be hinting at the following:
i)
We had an inconsistent physical theory about the world (or about the
atom).
ii)
That theory led to “empirical predictions [which] were
spectacularly successful”.
iii)
Therefore it is possible that the world itself
is inconsistent. (Or more strongly: The world is
inconsistent.)
It
must be stressed here that the meaning of the word “inconsistent”
is very different to the meaning of the word “contradictory” (or
“paradoxical”). Something can indeed be inconsistent because it contains contradictions. Though can't something be inconsistent
without also containing (logical) contradictions?
Here's
a passage
from Priest on an aspect of quantum mechanics that he sees as being
relevant to dialetheism:
“Unobservable
realms, particularly the micro-realm, behave in a very strange way,
events at one place instantaneously affecting events at others in
remote locations.”
Priest
gives another example of quantum happenings. This example is one of
radioactive decay. He writes:
“[S]uppose
that a radioactive atom instantaneously and spontaneously decays. At
the instant of decay, is the atom integral or is it not?”
Now
for the traditional logic of this situation. Priest
continues:
“In
both of these cases, and others like them, the law of excluded middle
tells us that it is one or the other.”
Couldn't
the atom be
neither
integral nor
non-integral when it instantaneously and spontaneously decays?
(Priest talks of either/or and “one or the other”; not
neither/nor.) Or, alternatively, at time
t, x
may not be an atom at all!
So
what of Priest's own (logical) conclusion when it comes to atomic
decay? He claims that the aforementioned atom “at the point of
decay is both integral and non-integral”. This isn't allowed –
Priest says - if the law
of excluded middle
has its way. After all, the law of excluded middle tells us that the
the atom must either
be integral or nonintegral; not “both integral and non-integral”.
Note:
1)
Some of the quoted words and passages from Graham Priest in the above are taken from the 'Everything
and Nothing'
seminar – a Robert Curtius Lecture of Excellence at Bonn University
- which Priest gave. I relied on both the transcript and the video
itself. However, I've edited a lot of what Priest says in that
seminar to make it more comprehensible. For example, I removed many of
the uses of the word “so”, added full stops, commas and suchlike.
Hopefully, the philosophical content is kept intact. None of this
applicable to the words and passages I quote which come from Priest's
papers.
*) See my ‘Graham Priest — and Martin Heidegger! — on Nothing (1)’ and my 'Graham Priest & Martin Heidegger Take Language on Holiday: the Nothing (2)'.
*) See my ‘Graham Priest — and Martin Heidegger! — on Nothing (1)’ and my 'Graham Priest & Martin Heidegger Take Language on Holiday: the Nothing (2)'.
No comments:
Post a Comment