i) Introduction
ii) Panpsychism?
ii) Panpsychism?
iii) Idealism and Anti-Realism
iv) Kant's Transcendental Idealism
v) The Copenhagen Interpretation
Donald
Hoffman's philosophical position is called conscious
realism.
He opposes that position to panpsychism and to Kant's transcendental
idealism.
In
terms of panpsychism: there are clear distinctions between Hoffman's
conscious realism and panpsychism. However, there are very clear and
strong similarities too. (In one place, Hoffman does
say
that he accepts what he sees as one type of
panpsychism
– the one that's not, in his eyes, “dualist”.)
If
we turn to Kant.
Hoffman
is against Kant's transcendental
idealism
for the primary reason that he doesn't deem it to be scientific.
Nonetheless, his arguments against Kant are neither convincing nor
does he distinguish his own position strongly enough from
transcendental idealism.
As
for anti-realism.
Hoffman
hardly mentions it. Nonetheless, he does mention the Copenhagen interpretation of
quantum mechanics favourably. In fact he uses it (in various places)
in order to defend his own position of conscious realism. The thing
is that Hoffman makes the Copenhagen interpretation seem idealist in nature. That said, he's hardly the first person to have done so (see
here).
And
on the subject of idealism.
This
piece argues that Hoffman's conscious realism is a new-fangled take
on idealism (i.e., idealism with mathematical and scientific knobs on
it). Hoffman will deny this and he'll do so for various reasons.
Primarily, Hoffman will do so because he does indeed believe that
there's a “reality” out there. (He often uses the word “reality”
positively – that there is a reality
- many times; despite the fact that he's just written a book called
The
Case Against Reality.)
Nonetheless, Hoffman also argues that we haven't got direct (or
even indirect) access to that reality. Instead, we've only got access
to the contents of consciousness. And that's still the case even if
those contents belong to some kind of collective of consciousnesses
(i.e., that of a collective of what Hoffman calls “conscious
agents”).
Panpsychism?
Professor
Donald Hoffman
is explicit about his position on panpsychism.
He
writes:
“Conscious
realism is not panpsychism, nor does it entail panpsychism.”
Of
course it can now be said that even if
Hoffman's conscious
realism
(CR) isn't identical to panpsychism - and also that it doesn't
“entail panpsychism”, that still doesn't mean that it has nothing
in common with it at all. It may even be the case that Hoffman's
conscious realism has a lot in common with panpsychism.
Hoffman
then makes various distinctions between his own position of conscious
realism
and panpsychism. He
states:
“Conscious
realism, together with MUI [multimodal
user interface]
theory, claims that tables and chairs are icons in the MUIs of
conscious agents, and thus that they are conscious experiences of
those agents. It does not claim, nor entail, that tables and chairs
are conscious or conscious agents.”
That
last sentence is of
course directly and clearly aimed at panpsychism. That being said,
not many (if any) panpsychists argue that tables and chairs are
“conscious agents”. They simply argue that tables and chairs (or
their many parts!) are conscious or that they
have
(whatever that may mean)
experience. (More of which in a moment.)
The
rest of the Hoffman quote above makes
some correct
distinctions between panpsychism and conscious realism. For one,
panpsychists most certainly don't
claim that “tables and chairs are icons in the MUIs of conscious
agents”. And neither do they claim that tables and chairs are the
“conscious experiences of [] agents”. More importantly (unlike
conscious realism), panpsychists do
claim that “tables and chairs [or their many parts] are conscious”;
though they rarely (if ever) claim that they're also “conscious
agents”. (This raises the question: What
does Hoffman mean by “agent”?)
Of
course there are different types of panpsychism and not all
panpsychists would be keen on using the precise words “tables and
chairs are conscious”. Instead, some panpsychists would say that
tables and chairs are made up of entities which contain
(or have) “phenonemenal
properties/qualities”
(or
“(proto)phenomenal
properties”).
This clearly isn't as grand as claiming that tables and
chairs are “conscious”. (I
don't use the term “qualia”
here because that will lead to unclarity.)
And
it's certainly less grand that claiming that tables and chairs are
conscious
agents.
However,
one part of Hoffman's story does seem to chime in with panpsychism.
Take this
passage:
“The
story that there was first the Big Bang and then, billions of years
of later, life, and then, hundreds of millions of years later,
consciousness, is fundamentally wrong. It's the other way around.
Consciousness is fundamental.”
Most
panpsychists would be very happy with Hoffman's sentence above.
Nonetheless, although they believe that “consciousness is
fundamental”, panpsychists and Hoffman have very different takes on
those three words. Put simply. Consciousness is fundamental to
panpsychists in the sense that all things have various degrees of
consciousness (or experience). To Hoffman, on the other hand,
consciousness is fundamental
in that the contents of an individual's consciousness (or the
contents of various collectives of conscious agents) is
literally constitutive of reality or the whole of the universe (as
well as everything in it).
Both
panpsychists and conscious realists agree that consciousness (or
experience) isn't an
“emergent property”
at all: it's been around since the Big Bang. Thus if consciousness
has been with the universe (as it were) since the Beginning, then the
issue of the emergence of consciousness becomes a non-problem.
Panpsychists
tend to think of consciousness (or phenomenal properties or
experience) as being “fundamental” in the sense that it exists
all the
way
down and
all the way up.
(That is, all the way down to particles and all the way up to human
beings.) Hoffman, on the other hand, stresses the fundamentality of
consciousness by writing it into the story at the Big Bang (actually,
just after). Having said that, these two emphasises work perfectly
well together. That is:
i)
If we have consciousness all the way down to particles,
ii)
then that's precisely because we had particles - and therefore
consciousness - (just after) the Big Bang.
Thus
these two positions fit perfectly well together.
To
repeat. Hoffman's position can be seen as a take on panpsychism in
that he states that “consciousness is fundamental”. (Three words
which many panpsychists often use together - see here.) Panpsychism also rejects the emergence of consciousness from the
physical and stresses, instead, that it's not the case that (to use
Hoffman's words) it's “a latecomer in the evolutionary history of
the universe” that “aris[es] from complex interactions of unconscious matter and fields”. Instead, panpsychists believe
that there's consciousness (or there are phenomenal
properties)
all the way down to the particle and all the way up to the animal
brain. Thus there's no need for (radical) emergence.
Idealism
and Anti-Realism
On
the surface at least, Hoffman seems to take a very strong
idealist
position when he says that “brains
and neurons do not exist unperceived”.
(This is exactly what Bishop
Berkeley
argued; thought not, of course, about “brains and neurons”.) Now
this isn't
an expression of anti-realism
because an anti-realist wouldn't say that any x
doesn't
exist “when unperceived”. He'd simply say that our perceptions
“colour” what it is we take to exist. And there's no way around
that.
All
this displays the very common problem of conflating (or confusing)
idealism and anti-realism.
Despite
having just stated that, there
is a
strong sense in which one can
derive idealist conclusions from anti-realist statements. That is:
i)
If we describe things as “brains" and "neurons”,
iia)
and those descriptions are contingent - and dependent – upon
persons/observers, concepts, theories, etc.,
iii)
then perhaps we may
as well
conclude that brains and neurons “do not exist unperceived”.
That
is, brains and neurons (as well as other objects) don't exist until
we describe/observe them. (This echos, to some extent at least, the
debate which surrounded Niels Bohr's Copenhagen
interpretation of quantum mechanics – see later section.) That's
true enough. However, why embrace the idealist conclusion that
everything that exists only does so in the minds of persons? That
route leads to idealism, subjectivism,
solipsism
and woo.
In
addition, what does Hoffman mean when he states that brains and
neurons “have
no causal power”?
I ask that question because he doesn't explain it in the passages
just quoted (though he may well do elsewhere). What's more, he
concludes that this lack of causal power is “why
we've never been able
to boot up consciousness from neural activity”. So what does all
that mean?
Kant's
Transcendental Idealism
Hoffman's
main problem with
Immanuel Kant's
position on noumena
is that he believes that it's not scientific. Or, less strongly, he
believes that Kant's position doesn't look promising from a scientific perspective.
As
Hoffman
puts it
about one “interpretation” of Kant:
“This
interpretation of Kant precludes any science of the noumenal, for if
we cannot describe the noumenal then we cannot build scientific
theories of it.”
Yet
Hoffman's own conscious
realism
isn't a scientific theory either. (Sure, it's clearly the case that
Hoffman believes that it is.) He then says
that
“[c]onscious
realism, by contrast, offers a scientific theory of the noumenal,
viz., a mathematical formulation of conscious agents and their
dynamical interactions”.
Hoffman
often defends his conscious realism by talking about its
“mathematical models”, etc (or by using the words above – i.e.,
“a mathematical formulation”). Despite that, only the
mathematical models or “formulations” used in conscious realism
are scientific (or mathematical). All the additions to that are
examples of speculative philosophy. So this isn't that unlike people
using mathematics and scientific terminology to defend - or back up -
astrology, astral travelling, ley lines, Creationism, etc. (This
aspect of Hoffman's conscious realism can't be tackled now. I've
tackled it here.)
In
addition, if conscious realism really “offers a scientific theory
of the noumenal”, then it's not the noumenal
that it's offering a scientific theory of. Of course this may be
terminological pedantary in that, to Hoffman, the noumenal isn't in
fact noumenal
at all.
Thus he believes that he can
offer a scientific theory of it. Kant, on the other hand, created a
theory in which noumena were – by
definition
– not only beyond science, but also beyond Hoffman's cognitive agents.
Hoffman
then expresses a position that isn't
at odds
with either anti-realism or Kant's transcendental
idealism.
He writes:
“Many
interpretations of Kant have him claiming that the sun and planets,
tables and chairs, are not mind-independent, but depend for their
existence on our perception. With this claim of Kant, conscious
realism and MUI theory agree. Of course many current theorists
disagree.”
The
wording in the above isn't quite right. Hoffman says that Kant
believed that
“the
sun and planets, tables and chairs, are not mind-independent, but
depend for their existence on our perception”.
Surely
it's best to say that some
things
(whatever they are) exist mind-independently. The problem is that
they don't exist as
the sun, planets, tables and chairs. That is, the fact that we see
these things this way is a result of our contingent modes of
“perception”; as well as our concepts, theories, languages, etc.
However, this is still not idealism because Kant's noumena
exist.
In addition, they aren't the contents of consciousness. So this is
transcendental idealism; not immaterialism
or subjective
idealism.
To
sum up. Whatever is “behind” (or the cause of) our perceptions is
not itself dependent on consciousness (or on our perceptions).
The
Copenhagen Interpretation
Hoffman
states
the following:
“Scientists
believe that space, time, and objects exist even if they're not
perceived. That's a fundamental assumption of most.”
So
let's reiterate what's just been said above (i.e., before the
subheading). Scientists (or at least some/most of them) do
believe that objects exist even when not perceived. However, when
they are perceived, then they're given (as it were) a determinate
form – a form which is down to our contingent theories,
experiments, perceptions/observations, concepts, languages, etc.
Secondly,
not all
- or even
most
-
scientists “believe that space, time, and objects exist even if
they're not perceived”. There have been (for many years) many
physicists working on the non-existence
of both space and time,
for example. (Admittedly, that's a question of the very existence of
space and time and it has little to do with our perceptions.) In
addition, scientists aren't philosophers. Thus most scientists have
little time for phrases like “objects exist even if they're not
perceived”.
This
leads us to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics.
Hoffman
often applies the Copenhagen
interpretation
to the “classical” (or macro) scale. (Indeed Hoffman himself
mentions the Copenhagen interpretation on a few
occasions and at one points says that "most
proponents of the Copenhagen interpretation embrace it only for the
microscopic realm".)
For example, here's
Hoffman applying it
to DNA:
“For
instance, [conscious realism] entails that DNA does not exist when it
is not perceived. Something exists when we don’t look that causes
us, when we do look, to perceive DNA, but, whatever that something
is, it’s not DNA.”
Perhaps
this is a bad example because at least DNA is a microphenomenon,
if not a subatomic
phenomenon. (Though DNA is determined by – and dependent upon -
quantum phenomena.) Elsewhere, however, Hoffman applies exactly the
same argument to brains (as a whole), cups, trees, and other everyday
macro-objects. Now, to state the obvious, there's a vast difference
between a electron (for example) and a tree (for example).
Another
point is that
Niels Bohr
didn't
embrace idealism. To put it simply. There's also a big difference
between the stress on how we gain
access
to (as it were) reality and the idealist position that it's all
about what goes on in one's head.
(Or within what Hoffman deems to be a Collective
Head.)
Anti-realists accept that there is a mind-independent world. However, human beings only gain access to that world through their brains,
consciousnesses, concepts, languages, etc. Idealism, on the other
hand, seems to have it that literally everything is in the minds of
subjects (or agents).
And, if that's correct, then that puts idealism and anti-realism in
radically different places. Yet, as is the case on so many occasions,
anti-realism is basically seen as idealism (or, at the least, as a
variety of idealism). Having said that, what Hoffman himself argues
doesn't
make
this distinction clear. And, because of that, it can be argued that
Hoffman's position is idealist rather than anti-realist.
No comments:
Post a Comment