The
use of the words “deflating quantum mechanics” isn't meant in the
sense of offering any challenge to quantum mechanics (QM) itself. Of course
not. For a start, I'm not a physicist. (One would need to be a great
physicist to challenge the fundamentals of quantum theory.) This piece, instead, is primarily aimed at the interpretations of QM by the layperson and indeed even
by some physicists. In other words, quantum theory is fine by me.
What I do have a problem with is commentators deliberately
attempting to make QM even more (as it's often put) “weird” than it actually is. In addition, there's
also of the problem of people focusing entirely on quantum weirdness.
More
relevantly, it's argued that this quantum weirdness is largely brought about when
people use images, pictures or analogies which are only applicable to
the everyday world, and then applying them to the quantum realm. This - almost by definition - must surely be like pushing square shapes into round holes.
In other words, it's bound to make QM weird/er.
***********************
It
would seem that one of the main positions advanced in this piece is
partly contradicted by a well-known quote from Albert Einstein. Namely:
“If
I can't picture it, I can't understand it.”
So despite Einstein's words, it can also be said:
If you can picture the phenomena of quantum mechanics, then you don't understand them.
Werner Heisenberg, for example,
argued that all the imagistic or analogical descriptions of QM are
problematic. More precisely, he stated the
following:
“Progress
in science has been bought at the expense of the possibility of
making phenomena of nature immediately and directly comprehensible to
our way of thought.”
In
other words, in order to make the scientific
scientists have relied on images, pictures and analogies which simply don't do the (complete) job. On the other hand, when scientists don't use such analogies, pictures or images, then QM is incomprehensible to “our way of thought”.
“phenomena of nature immediately and directly comprehensible to our way of thought”,
scientists have relied on images, pictures and analogies which simply don't do the (complete) job. On the other hand, when scientists don't use such analogies, pictures or images, then QM is incomprehensible to “our way of thought”.
There's
a deep problem here - at least for laypersons!
So what if it's partly the overuse of
imagery and analogies which makes QM seem so weird? Sure, QM is indeed weird. Nonetheless, using images,
picture and analogies which are applicable to the macro-scale (then
applying them to the micro-scale) can't help but make things weirder.
On the other hand, without imagery and the requisite mathematics, how
does any layperson or even physicist know that QM is weird at all?
It's
not only laypersons who have problems with “picturing” the
phenomena of QM - physicists do too. And since the failures (or
limits) of the imagination have just been been
stressed, here's the philosopher Ernan
McMullin stating
the following:
“If
we cannot quite imagine what they are, this is due to the distance of
the microworld from the world in which our imaginations were formed,
not to the existential shortcomings of electrons...”
Of
course all this depends on what exactly is meant by the word
“picturing” or “imagining”. It also depends on what's meant
by the words “understanding quantum mechanics”. Sometimes the
problem is also to do with the concepts we use to describe
QM phenomena. In other words, it's not only about imagery.
Take
a classic example: “wave-particle
duality”.
Perhaps
part of this problem is that the wave description isn't very apt in
the first
place.
That is, waves at the subatomic level aren't like waves in the sea, in your bath or even like waves at
all.
(The graphic representations of the “peaks and troughs” of the
interference
pattern,
for example, may not help.) This is why Erwin Schrodinger, for one,
decided to call them “wave functions” instead of "waves". In other words,
the wave description (even if only analogical) was never satisfactory
to Schrodinger and indeed to many other physicists.
So
what about particles?
The
American philosopher Ernest Nagel
once discussed the “puzzling characteristics” of particles. These
puzzling characteristics were seen to have been “incompatible”. (The word “incompatible” isn't a synonym of
“contradictory”.) More precisely, Nagel
argued that electrons are
“construed
to have features which make it appropriate to think of them as a
system of waves”.
Yet,
on the other hand, electrons “also have traits which lead us to
think of them as particles”.
Since
waves and particles have just been discussed, it's worth noting here
what the astrophysicist and writer John Gribbin
has to say on this. Gribbin ostensibly takes an extreme
position on this part-rejection of analogies, images and pictures. He
writes:
“In
the world of the very small, where particle and wave aspects of
reality are equally significant, things do not behave in any way that
we can understand from our experience of the everyday world...all
pictures are false, and there is no physical analogy we can make to
understand what goes on inside atoms. Atoms behave like atoms,
nothing else.”
It
can of course be said that even if it's correct that
“all
pictures are false, and there is no physical analogy we can make to
understand what goes on inside atoms”,
then
it may still be the case that (at least for laypersons) that's
all we've got. Indeed without the mathematics, all we have are
pictures, images and analogies. So we'd better make do with all that.
And surely John Gribbin isn't arguing that pictures, images and
analogies serve no purpose. Indeed he can't be arguing that because
his books make extensive use of them. Having said that, all Gribbin's
pictures, images and analogies do come with words of warning (as can
be seen in the quote above).
In
fact we can even say that the very use of the words “particle”
and “wave” may mean that Gribbin himself is using pictures or images
and/or being analogical. That is, if “in the world of the very
small” it's the case that
“things
do not behave in any way that we can understand from our experience
of the everyday world”,
then
why is Gribbin using the words “particle” and “wave” in the
first place?
Concepts
It's
not only QM that's the problem here.
According
to Freeman Dyson (who was talking about a “new theory [of]
black holes”), the problem was that
Stephen Hawking (at least at that point) was “still groping in the
dark for concepts which will make his theory [of black holes] fully intelligible”.
All this depends on what Dyson meant by “concepts”. After
all, he might have only been referring to mathematical
concepts.
In fact Dyson continued by saying
that
“[a]s
usual when a profoundly original theory is born, the equations come
first and a clear understanding of their physical meaning comes
later”.
So
not only is it the case that the mathematics isn't equal to the later
images, pictures and analogies which people use for physical
phenomena: at first the mathematics isn't even equal to anything
“physical” at all. Or, more precisely, the maths isn't equal to
the “physical meaning” which may - or will - “come later”.
This
shouldn't be a surprise because mathematics itself is an abstract realm
and numbers and equations (not their written symbols, etc.) are said
(at least by some philosophers and physicists) to be “abstract
objects”. Thus the equations Dyson referred to only became (as it were) concrete when
given a “physical meaning” or when applied (in this case) to
black holes.
So
here we have a disjunction between
mathematics and reality/nature that's only brought together when the
mathematics is given a physical meaning or when applied to reality.
However, even then it can be said that the disjunction still exists
in a strong way. This means that whereas many scientists stress the
unity of maths and physical reality, the opposite (as with string theory!) can
also be stressed.
So
we can still ask this question:
Freeman
Dyson talked about the concepts which will make the theories of
physics fully intelligible... but fully intelligible to whom?
Was
it to himself and Stephen Hawking? To other physicists
generally? Or to laypersons?
Scales and Levels
Richard
Feynman once wrote (when talking about an electron taking “many
paths” at the same time) the
following:
“[Quantum
mechanics] describes nature as absurd from the point of view of
common sense. And it fully agrees with experiment. So I hope you can
accept nature as She is – absurd.”
Perhaps
when Feynman used the words “common sense”, that common sense
position may primarily be a result of attempting to think of (or
visualise) what happens at the quantum-mechanical scale in the same
way in which one thinks of (or visualises) what happens at the
everyday scale.
Feynman
himself singled one such scale: the scale of the atom. He said that
“if
an apple is magnified to the size of the earth, then the atoms in the
apple are approximately the size of the original apple”.
We
also
have this from the nuclear physicist Kenneth W. Ford:
“For
example, to picture the nucleus, whose size is about 10-4
to 10-5
of the size of the atom, one may imagine the atom expanded to, say,
10,000 feet or nearly two miles... A golf ball in the middle of New
York International Airport is about as lonely as the proton at the
center of the hydrogen atom.”
Think
also the extra dimensions of string theory. Only four of string
theory's extra dimensions are observable. (That's if you can
literally observe macro-object-free spacial or time dimensions.)
Even
if extra dimensions do exist, they may still be (or are) incredibly small; as
well as “compacted”.
Thus the very idea of extra dimensions bears little relation to those
portrayed in horror and science-fiction films. Indeed, way back in
1926, the extra dimension
suggested by Oskar Klein
was thought be curled up and too small to be detectable. Thus only
something equally small could (as it were) live in this extra dimension.
And
strings themselves are fantastically
smaller than protons, neutrons and electrons. Let Freeman
Dyson explain by going even further with superstrings:
“First,
the entire universe. Second. The planet Earth. Third, the nucleus of
an atom. Fourth, a superstring. The step in size from each of these
things to the next is roughly the same.The Earth is than the visible
universe by about twenty powers of ten. An atomic nucleus is smaller
than the Earth by twenty powers of ten. And a superstring is smaller
than a nucleus by twenty powers of ten. That gives you a rough
measure of how far we have to go in the domain of the small before we
reach superstrings.”
In
any case, things at different scales (or things of different types)
display remarkably different kinds of behaviour.
Take
fleas, which can jump 100 times their own height. Take the
bacteria that survive below freezing point. And on the moon,
astronauts can float. However, these examples are still in a
different logical space to the things which occur at the quantum
scale. At the QM scale, some things are deemed to be "paradoxical" and
even "logically contradictory". Nothing a flea or astronaut does can be
described that way.
So
when we're talking about the subatomic scale, things are almost bound
to be fundamentally different. And when we get down to the scales
tackled by string theory, then you'd hardly expect the kind of things
you experience in your local pub.
Scales
and Superposition
There's
a big problem with this emphasis on the importance of scales when it
comes to QM. This means that it will need to be said why it is that these
scales (i.e., the micro and macro scales) should make such a profound
difference to things.
Take
superposition.
It's
often argued that superposition
is only applicable at the micro-scale. It's also argued that it
“cancels out” at the
macro-scale. More technically, it's said that when there are many
superpositions at the quantum level, then when such superpositions
are taken together, they produce a macro-state that is “definite”.
That is, such a “probabilistic collapse” would result in a definite
statistical process at the macro-level.
Nonetheless,
this very-neat division also needs to be explained: it has
been rejected.
Put
simply, there are good reasons to expect superpositions at the
macro-level too. Indeed there are “interpretations” (for example,
Hugh Everett's) which
state that superpositions do occur at the macro-level: it's just that
we only experience one such state of each superposition.
We
can also take Professor Brian Greene's general
point about this far-too-neat micro/macro division:
“It's
not as though the universe comes equipped with a line in the sand
separating things that are properly described by quantum mechanics
from things properly described by general relativity. Dividing the
universe into two separate realms seems both artificial and clumsy.”
This
position seems to back up a point Roger Penrose has made about how different
levels of description (which, he argues, are brought about by the
effect of “measurement” or observation) determine Greene's “line
in the sand” between the quantum realm and the “classical”
realm. In Penrose's
own words:
“Since
randomness comes in, quantum theory is called probabilistic. But
randomness only comes in when you go from the quantum to the
classical level. If you stay down at the quantum level, there's no
randomness. It's only when you magnify something up, and you do what
people call 'make a measurement'. This consists of taking a
small-scale quantum effect and magnifying it out to a level where you
can see it. It's only in that process of magnification that
probabilities come in.”
Thus Penrose particularly notes how randomness is a consequence of
observing quantum phenomena at the “classical level”. Nonetheless, this can still be
deemed to be an epistemic problem, rather than an ontological one.
That is, the probabilities (or randomness) arise not from the
ontology of the quantum world, but from our epistemic access to it.
******************************
No comments:
Post a Comment