Tuesday 7 June 2022

Was Quantum Physicist Werner Heisenberg an Idealist? (Part One)

Bernardo Kastrup, Deepak Chopra and other idealists have attempted to initiate Werner Heisenberg into the idealist camp. Are they right to do so?

(i) Introduction 
(ii) Heisenberg on 19th-Century Materialism 
(iii) Heisenberg on Dialectical Materialism 
iv) Heisenberg on Einstein’s Materialism and Realism
(v) Heisenberg on Positivism and Idealism
(vi) What is Materialism? 
(vii) Materialism Through the Eyes of Contemporary Idealists

Almost all the quotes from Werner Heisenberg in the following essay are taken from his book Physics and Philosophy: The Revolution in Modern Science. This book began life as Heisenberg’s 1955–6 Gifford lectures at the University of St Andrews (Scotland). It was first published in book form in 1958.

Introduction

Idealists, anti-materialists, New Agers and mystics often quote and mention Werner Heisenberg to back up what they already believe anyway. In other words, when you look into this, it can quickly be seen that virtually no contemporary idealist became an idealist due to his research into quantum mechanics. Instead, what nearly always happened is that such people became idealists for exclusively philosophical and/or spiritual reasons - and only then did they look to quantum mechanics for scientific backup.

Take these words from the idealist Deepak Chopra:

“The possibility of a mental universe has a strong lineage going in the quantum era, but present-day physicalists (physicists who accept the physical nature of reality as a given) feel free to dismiss or ignore figures as towering as Max Planck, Werner Heisenberg, and John von Neumann.”

Now take these words from an idealist (see here) who believes that he has “proved” that heaven exists (as in his book, Proof of Heaven) — Dr Eben Alexander:

“We live in a mental universe, projected out of consciousness, just as Heisenberg realized [].”

Despite my use of the term “mystics” earlier, the idealist Bernardo Kastrup warns against such (critical or negative) readings of contemporary idealism. Kastrup writes:

“We are often misinterpreted — and misrepresented — as espousing solipsism or some form of ‘quantum mysticism,’ so let us be clear: our argument for a mental world does not entail or imply that the world is merely one’s own personal hallucination or act of imagination. Our view is entirely naturalistic: the mind that underlies the world is a transpersonal mind behaving according to natural laws. It comprises but far transcends any individual psyche.”

It can easily be seen here that Kastrup is merely jumping out of the frying pan into the fire.

That is, Kastrup believes that forsaking what used to be called subjective idealism (which many people have also seen as a kind of solipsism) to embrace what was once called objective idealism (now, in its updated form, often called either Universal Idealism or Cosmic Idealism) somehow means that his seemingly new-fangled idealism (i.e., with frequent mentions of science) isn’t “mysticism”. Yet Kastrup himself often talks of religious, spiritual and mystical matters in very direct relation to his own Cosmic Idealism — see here, here and here. (Kastrup ties his personal idealism to purely political matters too — see here.)

And then we even have a long and wild jump from Heisenberg’s stress on measurements to Kastrup’s “transpersonal mind” (see the ‘transpersonal movement’). As Shawn Radcliffe writes (in a website called Science and Nonduality):

“For Kastrup and his colleagues, these types of measurements [in quantum mechanics] can only be performed by a conscious observer. They write that inanimate objects like a particle detector can’t truly measure a particle. With the double-slit experiment, ‘the output of the detectors only becomes known when it is consciously observed by a person,’ writes Kastrup. Extending this to all of reality, he argues that a ‘transpersonal mind’ underlies the material world.”

So is talk of “a transpersonal mind” really any better than talk of a merely “personal” idealism? If anything, Cosmic Idealism is more mystical than subjective idealism. Thus using phrases like “according to natural laws” and often mentioning physics, neuroscience (see here) and the other sciences doesn’t salvage Kastrup’s Cosmic Idealism from mysticism.

Indeed why does Kastrup deny his mysticism in one breath (as in the quote above) only to openly embrace it in the next breath? In this an example of Kastrup’s supposed philosophical depth and subtlety or simply a case of him having his cake and eating it too?

Take Kastrup’s many discussions of Carl Jung and the latter’s extremely strong influence on him. (Here’s Kastrup “discussing the mystical aspects of Carl Jung”.) Some people, perhaps Kastrup at other times, deny that Jung was a mystic. It can also be conceded that the the word “mysticism” can be used as a mindless term of abuse, much like Kastrup’s very-often-used term “materialist”. (It’s worth stating here that the term “New Agers” isn’t an ad hominem. Many New Agers class themselves as “New Agers” — see here.)

Heisenberg on 19th-Century Materialism

Much-quoted passages such as the following are used to advance the Heisenberg-was-an-idealist position:

“But the atoms or the elementary particles or possibilities rather than one of things or facts.”

Apart from that passage (at least in itself) being neither a direct nor an indirect argument for idealism, we can move on to other quotes too. Take the idealists (in this case Deepak Chopra again ) who’ve written such things as the following:

“As Heisenberg put it, electrons and other particles are not real but exist only as ideas or concepts. They become real when someone asks questions about Nature, and depending on which question you ask, Nature obligingly supplies an answer.”

Elsewhere, we also have this passage in the website Science & Nonduality:

“This phenomenon led physicist Werner Heisenberg to write in 1958, ‘The idea of an objective real world whose smallest parts exist objectively in the same sense as stones or trees exist, independently of whether or not we observe them [] is impossible.’ [].”

Again, the two passages above are not expressions of idealism from Heisenberg. It’s true that an idealist position can be extracted from them. However, (to be rhetorical) anything can be extracted from anything if one tries hard enough.

Yet Heisenberg did indeed castigate 19th-century materialism and the materialism which existed immediately before the “quantum revolution” of the 1920s.

For example, Heisenberg put his position very simply when he wrote this passage:

“The Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory has led the physicists away from the simple materialistic views that prevailed in the natural science of the nineteenth century.”

And, elsewhere, Heisenberg wrote the following words (which are also often quoted — especially in the idealist memes found on Facebook and social media generally):

“The ontology of materialism rested upon the illusion that the kind of existence, the direct ‘actuality’ of the world around us, can be extrapolated into the atomic range. This extrapolation, however, is impossible [] atoms are not things.”

In basic terms, then, with the rise of quantum physics in the 1920s, some physicists (not only Heisenberg) came to believe that the nature of matter (or the concept of matter) had been fundamentally altered. Of course other physicists didn’t believe this (more of which later.)

Heisenberg on Dialectical Materialism

Just as many contemporary idealists conflate materialism itself with 19th-century materialism, so Heisenberg himself had two brands of materialism in mind when he made his critical remarks: 19th-century materialism (as a whole); and, more specifically, dialectical materialism.

Heisenberg quoted one Soviet dialectical materialist and physicist Dmitry Blochinzev in the following passage:

“Among the different idealistic trends in contemporary physics the so-called Copenhagen school is the most reactionary. The present article is devoted to the unmasking of the idealistic and agnostic speculations of this school on the basic problems of quantum physics.”

So according to this dialectical materialist (Blochinzev), idealism is “reactionary”. The Copenhagen interpretation of quantum physics is idealist. Therefore the Copenhagen interpretation is also reactionary.

Blochinzev’s main problem was that the Copenhagen interpretation didn’t abide by the dictates of dialectical materialism. Thus Blochinzev quoted Lenin to back himself up; and that passage, in turn, was quoted by Heisenberg. Thus:

[] ‘However marvellous, from the point of view of the common human intellect, the transformation of the unweighable ether into weighable material, however strange the electrons lack of any but electromagnetic mass, however unusual the restriction of the mechanical laws of motion to but one realm of natural phenomena and their subordination to the deeper laws of electromagnetic phenomena, and so on — all this is but another confirmation of dialectical materialism.’[].”

As one can see, this reads like a religious tract. Indeed Heisenberg himself picked up on this when he responded by saying that this defence of dialectical materialism (from Lenin)

“seems to degrade it [“quantum theory”] to a staged trial in which the verdict is known before the trial had begun”.

So one can see why Heisenberg (as it were) had in in for materialism if his main and most influential experiences of materialism was the dialectical materialism of the 1920s and beyond.

Elsewhere, and perhaps not specifically aiming his words at dialectical materialists, Heisenberg notes the problem with positions like Blochinzev’s and Lenin’s (which can also work as a warning to idealists) when he warned that

“the scientist should never rely on special doctrines, never confine his method of thinking to a special philosophy”.

The scientist should, instead,

“always be prepared to have the foundations of his knowledge changed by new experience”.

But it wasn’t only the dialectical materialists and 19th-century materialists Heisenberg had his eyes on.

Heisenberg on Einstein’s Materialism and Realism

Heisenberg was certainly against realism — or at least he was against what he called “dogmatic realism”. So what is the link between realism and materialism?

Heisenberg detected what he called “materialism” among his fellow physicists. And it’s here that, to my 21st-century mind, Heisenberg appeared to conflate materialism with realism...

… That is unless either materialism must lead to realism or realism must lead to materialism. Alternatively, do contemporary idealists view materialism as being an actual subset of realism? (Idealists, like Bernardo Kastrup, certainly tie materialism and realism very closely together — see here.)

In specific reference to Albert Einstein, Max von Laue and Erwin Schrodinger, Heisenberg wrote:

“However, all the opponents of the Copenhagen interpretation do agree on one point. It would, in their view, be desirable to return to the reality concept of classical physics or, to use a more general philosophic term, to the ontology of materialism. They would prefer to come back to the idea of an objective real world whose smallest parts exist objectively in the same sense as stones or trees exist, independently of whether or not we observe them.”

So, on Heisenberg’s reading, materialism is a kind of realism. And realists believe in what’s often called an “objective world”. In Heisenberg’s own words:

“Quantum theory does not allow a completely objective description of nature.”

Thus, being a philosophical position, materialism needn’t always be naturalist in nature (see here). That is, it needn’t be cognisant of the sciences and their findings. Indeed, in this case, clearly such realists or materialists were rejecting the findings of physics — or at least they were rejecting the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory. In other words, the scientists who were also realists (just like contemporary “analytic metaphysicians”) believed that their personal philosophies could trump the findings of physics. (See, for example, the philosopher E.J. Lowe doing so in the chapter here.) In more clear terns, because the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory — and perhaps quantum mechanics itself — went against both “classical physics” and realism, Einstein, von Laue, Schrodinger and Bohm (among others) believed that it must be wrong in some way. That is, their prior philosophies (as I read Heisenberg’s position) were telling them that the Copenhagen interpretation was wrong!

This is how Heisenberg himself put it:

“Thus Einstein hoped that beneath the chaos of the quantum might lie hidden a scaled-down version of the well-behaved, familiar world of deterministic dynamics.”

Yes, the above is an indirect reference to those famous hidden variables. Or in Heisenberg’s own words again, a reference to

“a deeper level of hidden dynamical variables that effect the system and bestow upon it merely an apparent indeterminism and unpredictability”.

Heisenberg’s problem with materialism also (at least partly) stemmed from accounts of what was deemed “objective” in physics. And, of course, any talk of what is objective has been tied to the philosophical positions of realism, not only to materialism.

In any case, Heisenberg himself once wrote:

“The ontology of materialism rested upon the illusion that the kind of existence, the direct ‘actuality’ of the world around us, can be extrapolated into the atomic range. This extrapolation is impossible, however.”

Of course this passage won’t work very well for contemporary idealists because Heisenberg clearly restricted his claim to “the atomic range”. Idealists, on the other hand, apply their position to the entire universe and literally everything in it. In other words, contemporary idealists have “extrapolated” what Heisenberg and other physicists said about the atomic range into the “the world around us”. And that is precisely what Heisenberg warned against.

(Heisenberg wasn’t actually warning idealists about this: he was warning those who demanded a “classical picture” of quantum theory.)

But do any of Heisenberg's criticisms of the realism of Einstein and others necessarily lead to (philosophical) idealism?

Heisenberg on Positivism and Idealism

Many idealists and anti-materialists also tend to conflate (or fuse) materialism with logical positivism — and logical positivism is the victim of a very special disdain.

Of course the logically positivism of the 1920s, 1930s and 1940s grew out of positivism, which dated back to the 19th century. That said, it does seem to be the case that Heisenberg mainly had logical positivism in mind in the passages quoted in the following. That’s not surprising, Heisenberg’s words date from 1955/6 — not long after the “demise of logical positivism”.

Ironically enough, Heisenberg himself has often been classed as a “positivist” (see here). Indeed he was very positive toward positivism in the 1920s and 1930s. However, he later changed his mind on the merits of positivism. (See here.) For example, much later (in 1955/6) he stated the following:

“It should be noticed at this point that the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory is in no way positivistic. For, whereas positivism is based on the sensual perceptions of the observer as the elements of reality, the Copenhagen interpretation regards things and processes which are describable in terms of classical concepts, i.e., the actual, as the foundation of any physical interpretation.”

In other words, if anything, it was positivism (i.e., not the Copenhagen interpretation) that was subjectivist, if not idealist! And that was certainly true if one bears in mind, for example, the (to use Heisenberg’s words) “sensual perceptions” which were stressed by logical positivist philosophers such as Rudolph Carnap (1891–1970)…

In actual fact, however, Carnap used phrases like “cross-sections of experience”. Still, Carnap’s cross-sections of experience were hardly “describable in terms of classical concepts”. Like “sense data”, they were actually highly-artificial terms of art (i.e., the inventions of philosophers), not what Heinsberg called classical concepts.

Heinsberg's position is made even clearer when he discussed (straight after tackling Bishop Berkeley’s idealism) what he called “empiricist philosophy” . Indeed, in the following passage, Heisenberg might very well have been discussing various logical positivists and sense-data theorists too. He wrote:

“Our perceptions are not primarily bundles of colors and sounds; what we perceive is already perceived as something, the accent here being on the word ‘thing,’ and therefore it is doubtful whether we gain anything by taking the perceptions instead of the things as the ultimate elements of reality.”

Heisenberg was even clearer about (as it were) positivist subjectivism (not positivist idealism) when he wrote the following:

“Certainly quantum theory does not contain genuine subjective features, it does not introduce the mind of the physicist as a part of the atomic event.”

Heisenberg continued by arguing that quantum theory

“starts from the division of the world into the ‘object’ and the rest of the world, and from the fact that at least for the rest of the world we use classical concepts in our description”.

What is Materialism?

As with so much in philosophy, then, Heisenberg’s position entirely depends on how he defined the term “materialism”. It also depends on what particular materialists actually believed at the times he spoke about materialism.

It also has to be kept in mind that it’s an obvious fact that before quantum mechanics, materialists — both philosophers and scientists — wouldn’t have had a (as it were) quantum take on matter… But that’s simply because no one did! Indeed even quantum physicists didn’t agree — or fully comprehend — the philosophical (or ontological) implications of quantum mechanics in the 1920s and well beyond.

So why do contemporary idealists single out the materialists of the 1920s and before and what Heisenberg had to say on them?

The point being made here is that there was never any necessary reason for materialists to believe that atoms are (to use Heisenberg’s word) “things”. That’s because materialists believed that atoms are things when most physicists believed — and some still do — that atoms are things. That said, when certain (quantum) physicists started to question that simple “classical picture”, then so too did many materialists. In other words, such materialists were taking their cue from physics.

So now let’s bring this issue right up to date.

Today there’s no reason why a materialist should ever have a problem with, say, the Lambda-CDM model. In this model, old-style “matter” only makes up 5% of the density level of the universe. That is, certain — perhaps many — physicists now believe that 95% of the universe is made up of dark matter and dark energy.

Again: the important point here is that (regardless of the accuracy of the technical details) many materialists go with the science — even if materialism is not itself a science.

Materialism Through the Eyes of Idealists

As already stated, many idealists and anti-materialists seem to conflate materialism with what many materialists believed in the 19th century — or at least up until (roughly) the 1920s. In other words, contemporary idealists have a view of materialism that might have been correct in the 19th century and the early 20th century. Yet even by the 1930s — if not before — this stereotype of materialism was no longer the case when it came to many (philosophical) materialists.

All this largely boils down to idealists and anti-materialists claiming that materialists believe that all matter — and indeed everything else — is what they call “tangible stuff”. Indeed the frequent claim used to be — and sometimes still is — that materialists believe that everything is made up of “hard particles”.

More relevantly, contemporary idealists can — and often do — bring up Heisenberg in this respect.

So at the heart of Heisenberg’s technical problem with materialism was his stress on the matter-energy (or matter-force) distinction.

For example, Heisenberg made things clear in the following passage:

“A clear distinction between matter and force can no longer be made in this part of physics, since each elementary particle not only is producing some forces and is acted upon by forces [].”

Despite those words, everything had already begun to change with field physics in the 19th century — which all (naturalist) materialists almost immediately took on board. Why was that? It was largely because such materialists (i.e., not all materialists) weren’t mindlessly committed to tangible stuff or to anything else like that — they were committed to the findings of physics and the other sciences. And physicists discovered fields (other than gravity) in the 19th century (see here).

In addition, when Einstein showed that matter and energy are interchangeable, many materialists immediately took that on board too. Thus, as an obvious consequence of that, many materialists also came to believe that energy — not matter — is (as it were) prima materia… Or at least they came to believe that matter is a form of energy.

And something similar occurred with the rise of quantum field theory.

Again, many materialists took quantum field theory on board. That is (as with Einstein’s equation of matter and energy), materialists came to see that fields — not energy — are prima materia; and therefore that energy and particles are properties of such fields.

The important point here, then, is (even if the technical details of physics are misinterpreted) that although there was a (radical) shift in a part of physics, many materialists still took on board these new findings, commitments and theories of physics.

So let the Australian philosopher Keith Campbell (1938-) sum up all the above in the following words:

“What the claim to materiality amounts to changes as physics changes. In the eighteenth century, (1) would assert that all events involving the body can be explained by reference solely to impact and gravitation among particles. And this is false, for the body is electromagnetic as well as mechanical. In the twentieth century, (1) embraces electromagnetism, for that is part of contemporary physics. The content of the claim that an object is material is relative to the physics of the time it is made.”

Conclusion

Finally, Heisenberg expressed a position which seems to chime in perfectly with what is called anti-realism — i.e., not idealism. (On some readings of metaphysical anti-realism, admittedly, it’s almost indistinguishable from idealism — see here.) That is, Heisenberg’s position strikes a middle way between realism and idealism.

Heisenberg began one passage with the following words:

“It has been pointed out before that in the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory we can indeed proceed without mentioning ourselves as individuals [].”

It can of course be said that claiming that the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory “can indeed proceed without mentioning ourselves as individuals” may not amount to much. After all, that may only be a formal requirement of the interpretation that it simply doesn’t mention (or it overlooks) the perspectives or experiences of individuals. Yet that, in itself, doesn’t mean that it isn’t based on individual experiences, minds, observers, etc.

But then Heisenberg continued:

[W]e cannot disregard the fact that natural science is formed by men. Natural science does not simply describe and explain nature; it is part of the interplay between nature and ourselves; it describes nature as exposed to our method of questioning.”

Here the very acceptance of what Heisenberg called “nature” hints at a non-idealist picture. More specifically, the phrase “the interplay between nature and ourselves” is an acknowledgement that, on the one hand, there is nature, and, on the other hand, we have ourselves. Yet surely in the idealist story there is only ourselves (i.e., according to Objective idealism or Cosmic Idealism) or even only oneself (i.e., according to Subjective Idealism).

Of course an idealist like Bernardo Kastrup would get around this by arguing that this nature (he prefers the word “reality”) is itself is part of Cosmic Consciousness (or that nature is a “projection” of a “collective consciousness”). So this is just a case of “disassociated” individuals (in this instance it just happens to be physicists) reconnecting with Cosmic Consciousness as it is instantiated in what is called nature.

Yet it is almost certainly the case that Heisenberg himself would have laughed at this position. That is, there is no evidence whatsoever that he would have endorsed this idealist reading of his own position.

*********************************

Notes:

(1) Heisenberg’s position above on “things” or individuals, as first stated in 1955/56 at the Gifford lectures, was philosophically replicated by the philosopher P.F. Strawson in his 1959 book, Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics.

(2) Why do idealists never quote the anti-subjectivist and anti-idealist words of Heisenberg in their articles and social-media memes? At least the passages from Heisenberg which idealists quote have also been referred to above.

*) Part Two is to follow. This will be a more (philosophically) technical account of Werner Heisenberg’s philosophy of physics as it relates to contemporary idealism.


Saturday 28 May 2022

Yes, Thomas Nagel, x can’t know what it’s like to be y

Owen Flanagan argued that Thomas Nagel was essentially asking, “What is it like for individual x to be individual y?

Owen Flanagan and Thomas Nagel
“Insofar as I can imagine this (which is not very far) it tells me only what it would be like for me to behave as a bat behaves. But that is not the question. I want to know what it is like for a bat to be a bat.”

— — Thomas Nagel (From his ‘What is it like to be a bat’. The passage is here.)

“If the problem is that every attempt to understand the mental life of another must be from a particular point of view, this is a problem every subject of experience has in understanding every other subject of experience. Bats play no essential role in the argument whatsoever.”

— — Owen Flanagan (From his book, Consciousness Reconsidered. The passage is here.)

Introduction

Firstly, the following is a statement of the broad — and perhaps obvious - position advanced in this essay:

No individual person can experience or instantiate another individual’s (to use Thomas Nagel’s words) “point of view”.

More simply, no individual can be another individual. Therefore no individual can instantiate or experience another individual’s point of view.

… But so what?

All the words above are in reference to Thomas Nagel’s position. (Thomas Nagel is an American philosopher.)

So let’s get to the heart of Nagel’s philosophical stance; at least as it was noted by the American philosopher Owen Flanagan (1949 — ).

Owen Flanagan

Firstly, Flanagan told us that Nagel has a problem with the situation that

“such a theory fails to capture what exactly conscious mental life is like for each individual person”.

Flanagan continued:

“Nagel’s continual mention of the way consciousness attaches essentially to a ‘single point of view’ indicates that this bothers him.”

More broadly, this is how Flanagan put things:

“Theorizing of the sort I have been recommending is intended not to capture what it is like to be each individual person but only to capture, in the sense of providing an analysis for, the type (or types) conscious mind and, what is different, consciousness person.”

So was Nagel making the blindingly-obvious logical point that x can’t be y? Sure, he might not have ever put it that simply… but that doesn’t matter.

Moreover, Nagel’s impeccable (if implicit) logical point (i.e., that x can’t be y) has little effect on either naturalism or physicalism. And that’s because both (if in basic terms) accept the law of identity.

Only an “individual person” can know “what it is like to be” that individual person. And Flanagan’s own take on this is that each individual has his, her or its own individual (causal) “hook-ups” to both himself/herself/itself and to the world. In detail:

“Naturalism can explain why only you can capture what it is like to be you. Only your sensory receptors and brain are properly hooked up to each other and to the rest of you so that what is received at those receptors accrues to you as your experiences.”

Flanagan continued:

“In the final analysis, your experiences are yours alone; only you are in the right causal position to know what they seem like. Nothing could be more important with respect to how your life seems and how things go for you overall [].”

And in more detail:

“It is because persons are uniquely causally well connected to their own experiences. They, after all, are the ones who have them. Furthermore, there is no deep mystery as to why this special causal relation obtains. The organic integrity of individuals and the structure and function of individual nervous systems grounds each individual’s special relation to how things seem for him [].”

Again, it is literally impossible for naturalism, physicalism or any other ism to get around this logical truth.

Of course even if it is the case that Nagel’s position is primarily motivated by the individual’s “point of view”, anti-physicalists may still argue that this isn’t the only (or even the main) argument against physicalism. That is, regardless of the logical uniqueness of the individual’s point of view, it’s still impossible to move from the physical (or from the brain) to consciousness or to experience. That is, no matter how strong and many the “correlations” are, there’s still something left out when it comes to the neuroscientific accounts of experiences, consciousness or “qualia”.

Another way to put this is that even if an individual human being or animal instantiated consciousness or experience but had no point of view (such as is the case with the lower animals), then a move from the physical to its experiences would still be problematic. After all, philosophers have long recognised the independence of consciousness from, particularly, self-consciousness and from all other higher-levels of mentality - and therefore from points of view too. Thus, in these cases, such animals don’t have a point of view. And that means that another individual can’t know what’s it’s like to have another’s point of view if that point of view isn’t instantiated in the first place.

X is Not Y

Thomas Nagel put his position clearly (if implicitly and tangentially) in the following way:

“This bears directly on the mind-body problem. For if the facts of experience — facts about what it is like for the experiencing organism are accessible only from one point of view, then it is a mystery how the true character of experiences could be revealed in the physical operation of that organism.”

And elsewhere (as quoted by Flanagan) Nagel also wrote:

“‘But when we examine their subjective character it seems that such a result is impossible. The reason is that every subjective phenomena is essentially connected with a single point of view, and it seems inevitable than an objective, physical theory will abandon that point of view.’”

In response to all that and more, Flanagan stated the obvious:

“If I am not you, I cannot grasp what it is like to be you.”

And Flanagan also put it almost as plainly in the following:

“Naturalism can explain why only you can capture what it is like to be you. Only your sensory receptors and brain are properly hooked up to each other and to the rest of you so that what is received at those receptors accrues to you as your experiences.”

Thus Flanagan pus the what-is-it-like-to-be show (with its hundreds — perhaps thousands — of articles, papers and books) largely down to the fact that an individual person can never be another individual (whether another human person or a different kind of non-human animal). Thus any given individual can never know what it is like to be that other individual.

Of course Flanagan put some technical neuroscientific meat on that basic claim by mentioning such things as “sensory receptors and [the] brain”. Still, it’s still an individual person’s sensory receptors and brain not being another individual's sensory receptors and brain that’s at the heart of this what-is-it-like-to-be story. That is, mentioning the extra detail that

“your sensory receptors and brain are properly hooked up to each other and to the rest of you so that what is received at those receptors accrues to you as your experiences”

is basically another way of saying that you can’t be someone (or some thing) else.

But why on earth is that (as it were) brute fact alone a threat to either naturalism or to physicalism?

In any case, Nagel often used the word “character” (as in “subjective character of experience”) to get his point across.

The Character of Another Individual’s Experiences

The following is Flanagan's take on Nagel’s word “character”:

“The equivocation is the source of the illusion that an understanding of some set of experiences necessarily involves grasping the character of these experiences.”

Here again we have the gross truth that one individual can’t be another individual. That is, this isn’t simply the case of not knowing what it is like to experience what another individual experiences…

It’s much more basic than that.

The point is that in order to experience what another individual experiences, we would need to be that other individual.

The following is the basic argument:

(i) If you or I were another individual, then you or I would know what is it like to experience what that other individual experiences. 
(ii) It is logically impossible for an individual to be another individual. 
(iii) Therefore it is logically impossible for you or I to know what it is like to experience what another individual experiences.

Flanagan provided a concrete example of this when he wrote the following:

“There is no incoherence in comprehending some theory that explains bat experiences without grasping exactly what bat experiences are like for bats. Indeed, the theory itself will explain why only bats grasp² their experiences.”

More generally:

“A theory of experience should not be expected to provide us with some sort of direct acquaintance with what the experiences it accounts are like for their owners.”

Here we have a distinction between a theory about a given experience (or type of experience) and actually being able to (as it were) experience that experience. Flanagan believes that naturalism provides such a theory. However, Flanagan also concedes that no individual can experience what another individual (whether a bat or another human person) experiences.

What’s more, Nagel’s position is both extreme and obvious.

It is so because Nagel advances the position (if only implicitly and tangentially) that if a given individual can’t literally become another individual, then any theory of that other individual's experiences (or, indeed, of any experiences) will always fail. Or as Flanagan put this point:

“The horn is easily avoided by seeing that its source lies in the unreasonable expectation that grasping a theory (grasp¹) should ‘open’ the experiences to us (grasp²). If we don’t grasp² bat experiences once we grasp¹ the theory that explains bat experiences, then we don’t really understand (grasp¹) the theory.”

Owen Flanagan’s Naturalism

It’s ironic that naturalism “can explain why only you can capture what it is like to be you”. That is, naturalism can explain why only you can know what it’s like to be you. However, naturalism can’t also enable the naturalist to experience what it is like to be you. And that’s because, again, “your sensory receptors and brain are properly hooked up to each other” and not properly hooked up to the naturalist or scientist studying you.

So Flanagan freely and happily admitted that “your experiences are yours alone”. And then he offered more detail when he argued that “you are in the right causal position to know what they seem like”. Flanagan even acknowledged that

“nothing could be be more important with respect to how your life seems and to how things go for you overall”.

And yet! -

[N]othing could be less consequential with respect to the overall fate of the naturalistic picture of things.”

So, again, apart from stating the obvious point that you (or anyone else) can’t be another individual, Flanagan also noted that this fact has almost zero consequence or relevance for either science or for naturalism.

But what about physicalism?

Physicalism?

Basically, Flanagan argued that the language of physics (or indeed any scientific language) can’t be used to describe experiences from a first-person perspective. That’s mainly because physics doesn’t even attempt to describe perspectives and experiences from a first-person point of view. Instead, physics (along with the other sciences) attempts to describe and/or explain first-person perspectives and experiences form a third-person point of view. (Daniel Dennett has had much to say on this in that he completely accepts what he calls heterophenomenology.)

In fact Flanagan widens this general point out by arguing that “everything physical” cannot be “expressed or captured in the languages of the basic sciences” (i.e., in the languages of “completed physics, chemistry, and neurophysiology”). In basic terms, then, that’s because even though first-person experiences and perspectives are indeed physically “realised” in the brain, they still can’t by “captured”, expressed or described in the languages of the basic sciences.

The position just expressed above is pitted against what Flanagan calls “linguistic physicalism”.

All this means that we have two positions which may, at least at first, seem to contradict one another:

(1) Flanagan wrote: “All there is, is physical stuff and its relations.” 
(2) Flanagan believes that not all physical stuff can be “captured in the languages of the basic sciences”.

Again, statement (1) is accepted primarily because even an individual’s experiences and perspectives are “realised” in physical stuff (in this case, the brain). Yet statement (2) tells us (if implicitly) that aspects of the brain are experienced from first-person “modes of presentation”.

In more concrete and specific terms, Flanagan continued:

“‘An experience of red’ is not in the language of physics. But an experience of red is a physical event in a suitably hooked-up system. Therefore, the experience is not a problem for metaphysical physicalism.”

Yet Flanagan happily acknowledges that

“no linguistic description will completely capture what a first-person experience of red is like”.

And that’s largely because physics — or the sciences generally — can’t get around the logical truth that x can never be y.

***************************

Notes on Qualia

(1) Even Daniel Dennett accepts that qualia are “real”… Or at least Flanagan believed that Dennett does when he wrote the following:

“Qualia are for real. Dennett himself says what they are before he starts quining. Sanely, he writes, ‘‘Qualia’ is an unfamiliar terms for something that could not be more familiar to each of us: the ways thing seem to us’ [].”

… But so what?

Sure — there are ways things seem to us. Okay. But where do we go from there?

Dennett may well accept qualia. However, he certainly doesn’t accept what he takes to be the one and only philosophical account of them — see here. (Incidentally, Owen Flanagan doesn’t believe that we need accept that one-and-only account.) That is, such qualia (at least on Dennett’s philosophical position) are mere “quicksilver” with very little scientific (or even philosophical) point.

(2) One definition of the technical term “qualia” is that it captures (to use Dennett’s words as used directly above) “the ways things seem to us”. But that definition can’t be right. Qualia are supposed to capture the ways things seem to each individual. So there is no collective quale and therefore no “us” when it comes to an individual quale. Thus the definition of qualia should be: The way things seem for each individual. In that sense, a quale of, say, red, at time t for subject S will be different to a quale of red at time t² for that very same subject S. Thus there isn’t even a single static seeming to any single quale for any given individual subject.

In that sense, then, the particularities of the (possibly) infinite numbers of qualia may even work against the strong anti-physicalist positions of qualiaophiles.