We
have many versions of semantic holism in the philosophy of language
and the philosophy of thought.
Take
Donald Davidson.
Davidson
believed that the
“account
of the truth-conditions for any one sentence is systematically
related to the account of the truth-conditions for a whole range of
other sentences”.
(We can now ask: How large must this range of other
sentences be?)
We
can clarify Davidson’s semantic holism in terms of the
systematicity of a concept-expression and its possession. As Michael
Luntley puts it:
“The
axiom governing any single concept expression does not itself specify
the meaning of the expression; it does so only in the context of an
overall theory that employs that axiom in a systematic manner to
compute the meaning of whole sentences in which the concept
expression figures.” (1999)
The
starting point of Davidson’s theory is Frege’s Context Principle
in which the meaning of an expression is determined by its context
and place within a truth-valued sentence. Davidson extends Frege’s
Context Principle to include other sentences in which the said
expression occurs. It's from this group of sentences (large or small)
that we can compute the expression’s meaning within the context of
an overall theory.
We
also have a well-known statement from Davidson on meaning-holism
that's sometimes taken as a criticism of holism; though, at other times,
simply taken as an explanation of the phenomenon.
In
his paper, ‘Truth and Meaning’, Davidson writes:
“If
sentences depend for their meaning on their structure, and we
understand the meaning of each item in the structure only as an
abstraction from the totality of sentences in which it features, then
we can give the meaning of any sentence (or word) only by giving the
meaning of every sentence (and word) in the language.” (1967)
This
may not mean that the individual speaker (or thinker) need understand
(or know) every word and sentence in the language at the moment of
his understanding: only that in effect the meaning of a word or
sentence is ultimately determined by - and depends upon - the entire
language (regardless of the complete understanding of the individual
speaker or thinker).
For
example, the possible moves in a game of chess are finite though very
large. It needn't be the case that the individual chess-player
understands (or knows) all the possible moves in the game of chess in
order to make a single move (or understand the rules of chess
generally).
The
same with definitions.
There
will come a time that the indefinite regress of definitions (or
definitions of definitions) will come to end when the original
definiendum comes back on the scene. However, it doesn't
follow that the individual speaker (or thinker) need go through this
indefinite regress in order to use (or understand) the word under
definition - even if an indefinite regress is entailed by the original
definition.
The
individual speaker (or thinker) needs to begin somewhere; just as the
epistemologist won't attempt to justify all his premises in an
argument of justification. Even the semantic sceptic needs
Wittgenstein’s ‘hinges’ to turn on in order to get his
sceptical show on the road.
References
Davidson,
Donald, 'Truth
and Meaning' (1967)
Luntley,
Michael, Contemporary
Philosophy of Thought: Truth, World, Content (1999).
No comments:
Post a Comment