What
is Philosophy?
It's
perhaps ironic that Ludwig
Wittgenstein's
rejection of metaphilosophy (or, at the least, his rejection of the
analogy between a metalanguage/object-language and
metaphilosophy/philosophy) can itself be seen as being
metaphilosophical in nature. (This position can be found in
Wittgenstein's Philosophical
Investigations; as well as
elsewhere.) After all, one needs to take a position beyond
(meta)
or “about” the possible relation between philosophy and a
metaphilosophy in order to see that relation as “nonsense”. Of
course we can say that, in this case, all sorts of philosophers have
therefore engaged in metaphilosophy.
However,
when philosophers like Wittgenstein have told us what philosophy is,
what they've really told us is what they think philosophy should
be. In
other words, their positions weren't descriptive:
they were normative.
Take
the
proto-analytic
philosophers of the late 19th
century and early 20th
centuries (e.g., Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein).
They
believed that all philosophy is (or should
be) the analysis of what they called “propositions”. Why did they
believe this? Basically it was because they also believed that
propositions captured the joints of reality or the world. (Or at
least the analysis of such propositions did.) Now, from a
metaphilosophical position (or
intuitively
- if one accepts intuitions), this seems like a remarkable claim. Why
should propositions have any direct relation to the world - never
mind be capable of uncovering its “deep
structure”?
This may of course be an intuitive response based on seeing
propositions as simply linguistic items; which wasn't seen to be the
case with these early analytic philosophers. Propositions were seen
as being part of world – at least of the abstract
world.
Not
long after this, it can be seen that other philosophers and schools
of philosophy also took what can be seen as a metaphilosophical - as
well as normative - position on the question “What is philosophy?”.
For
example, the logical positivists wanted to erase metaphysics from the
philosophical world. The ordinary language philosophers went back to
the position of seeing the fundamental importance of analysing
propositions. Except that this time they were thinking in terms of
natural-language statement rather than logical or abstract
propositions. From this position arose the metaphysical stance that
ordinary language itself is – or should be - paramount in
philosophy. Ignoring the nature of everyday language - “ordinary
language philosophers” argued - leads to “metaphysical nonsense”,
illusions and “meaninglessness”.
There's
also the explicit metaphilosophical question of whether philosophy
should be descriptive or “revisionary”
(i.e., normative). This was exemplified by, amongst others, Peter
Strawson
in his book Individuals:
An Essay
in Descriptive Metaphysics
(1959). One consequence of accepting a descriptive stance is to
believe that philosophy is – or must be - continuous with science.
Here
it's very clear that a decision as to whether one does descriptive or
revisionary philosophy is a metaphilosophical in nature. After all, a
philosopher could do both. Indeed another metaphilosopher may reject
this descriptive/revisionary “opposition” entirely.
First
Philosophy?
There
are of course massive philosophical assumptions involved in a belief
in a First Philosophy. Can there be such a thing as a First
Philosophy? And, even if there is such a thing, why should it be
ontology, logic, epistemology or even politics? Can such a First
Philosophy truly come before all other kinds of philosophy or is it
just a case that philosophers have assumed that without actually
displaying it?
Perhaps
more relevantly (that's if the questions just asked aren't in
themselves metaphilosophical), is First Philosophy metaphilosophy? Is
taking the position that ontology, logic, epistemology, ethics or
politics is a First Philosophy a metaphilosophical position. Does it
matter anyway?
It's
also quite possible that there can be a conflation between those
philosophers who believe that philosophy must have a First
Philosophy
and those very same philosophers being metaphilosophers. Unless, of
course, the championship of a particular First Philosophy is an
example of metaphilosophy!
Take
the case of Descartes.
Descartes
took epistemology
to be
First Philosophy - at least as seen from a 20th
century perspective. Indeed one well-known book of his is called
Meditations
on First
Philosophy.
(Descartes didn't use the word “epistemology”.)
Descartes
believed that the
Cogito
- and everything that followed from it - would be foundational; not
only to philosophy itself but also science. This is almost the same
position Husserl adopted some 200
years
later.
Husserl
himself developed the
“phenomenological method” in
order to enable philosophy to provide a “foundational
science”
of cognition whose results would then be used in science. Thus
Husserl believed that philosophy had a very distinct role. He also
believed that he knew exactly what that role is.
Further
back (as well as in less detail), ontology was once deemed to be
First Philosophy. (Ontology
–
or at least “metaontology” - is
experiencing a modest comeback in recent years.) In the 19th
century, it can be argued that Frege believed that
logic
is First Philosophy. In the 20th
century, analytic philosophers have variously seen the philosophy of
language and the philosophy of mind to be First Philosophy. (Though,
of course, they never used the words “first philosophy” -
certainly not with platonic capitals!)
Emmanuel
Levinas
and even Jacques Derrida can be seen as seeing ethics – or Ethics -
to be First Philosophy. (Levinas,
in his Totality
and Infinity,
actually said this.) However, in terms of Continental philosophy as a
whole, one can easily argue that most post-World War Two philosophers
saw politics (or, at the least, the
philosophy of politics
or even political
philosophy)
as being First Philosophy.
Politics
as First Philosophy?
Perhaps
the best and most interesting examples of seeing politics as First
Philosophy can be seen by those who advanced “critical
theory”.
The work of Jürgen Habermas can also be put in this mold.
Indeed, when such philosophers called their work “postmetaphysical
thinking”,
was that an acknowledgement that politics had become primary in their
philosophies?
Going
back in time, it can be argued that Martin Heidegger's believed
politics to be First Philosophy. However, it's certainly true that he
would haven't said that himself. Nonetheless, as an adherent of a
postmetaphysical
approach, Heidegger did see metaphysics as being strongly connected
to the ills of modern society. Surely that's a political
- or
at least a moral
- stance
on metaphysics and philosophy as a whole.
Ironically,
Heidegger's essentially conservative (or “reactionary”) position
influenced Derrida's own stance on the deconstruction
of Western metaphysics.
Derrida too placed ethics or politics in the First Philosophy
position. He too saw very strong connections between metaphysics and
bad politics or bad morality. (Again, Derrida, like Heidegger before
him, would never have put it this simply himself.) More precisely,
Derrida wanted to question the many “assumptions” of previous
Western philosophy. Why? Because he took a political and/or ethical
stance against all of them them; as well as against their
consequences. Thus politics was First Philosophy to Derrida.
Philosophy
and Science
One
of the most important metaphilosophical pursuits is seeing whether or
not philosophy is or is not a science. In addition, this pursuit will
also involve the adumbrating the similarities and dissimilarities
between philosophy and science. (A strong distinction between science
and philosophy was of course made by the early (as well as late)
Wittgenstein and some of the logical positivists.)
Firstly,
it can be argued that philosophical questions don't have empirical
answers. They can't be answered with recourse to experiment or
observation. (Timothy
Williamson,
Laurence
BonJour
and
others think otherwise.) In parallel to this, some philosophers have
argued that only science can answer questions which involve empirical
elements. However, surely it can't be the case that a question which
includes empirical elements has no philosophical elements. Indeed
even a question or statement that's seemingly entirely empirical must
include philosophical assumptions and may, as a consequence, need a
philosophical analysis.
Other
philosophers believe that philosophy is (or should be) continuous
with science. However, seeing science and philosophy as being
continuous is far from seeing them as being two aspects of the same
discipline.
Take
W. Quine after his logical positivist days.
Quine
too saw science and philosophy as being continuous. He didn't see
philosophy itself as being a science. Indeed he placed science in a
higher rank than philosophy. In simple terms, science told us “what
there is”,
and only then did philosophy (or logic and ontology) get to work on
what science has told us.
Three
Specific Examples
Analytic
Philosophy
Many
analytic philosophers (at least until relatively recently) certainly
wouldn't see the position – or positions! - of analytic
philosophers to be metaphilosophical in nature. Yet in order to see
philosophy as being (according to the Penguin
Dictionary of Philosophy)
"the disinterested pursuit of knowledge for its own sake"
(or
even to see it as being a – purely? - theoretical and technical
pursuit), one has to have taken various metaphilosophical positions
on philosophy itself. The analytic approach and the analytic style,
after all, didn't simply fall from the sky into the laps of
philosophers. Thus I can only presume that at least some analytic
philosophers studied a few philosophers who certainly couldn't have
been classed as analytic
philosophers.
Not that every analytic philosopher - and certainly not every student
of analytic philosophy - will have needed to engage in these
navel-gazing
reflections. It only needs to have been the original analytic
philosophers - as well as a few later ones - who did so. The rest
will have simply ridden on the backs of these prior metaphilosophical
reflections on the proper (or true) nature of philosophy.
It's
also very ironic and surprising (at least to me) that some analytic
philosophers have been influenced by a strain of Richard Rorty's (or
pragmatist) thought. They too see philosophy in broad terms. In terms
of politics, some of them believe that analytic philosophers should
be much more “politically committed”. And, in parallel, they
believe that philosophers should stop obsessing about many (or all?)
of those traditional and trite philosophical problems.
This
itself begs philosophical questions. Why be politically committed at
all? Moreover, why be committed to specific
political goals? I mention specificity because you can bet that such
(pragmatist) analytic philosophers will be committed to very specific
political goals. This can be expressed in another way by asking a
simple (though long) question:
If
a philosopher became committed to the wrong political goals and
actions, would such a proponent of “political commitment” be just
as happy with that as he would be if the philosopher concerned were
committed to his own political
goals?
I
doubt it.
Pragmatism
It
seems be clear the pragmatist position on philosophy (as with others)
is normative in nature. Perhaps, in at least certain cases, it's
also moral or political. By definition, most pragmatists believe that
philosophy should be a applicative
(indeed pragmatic) pursuit. Of course philosophical questions may
need to be asked as to what philosophical pursuits are practical and
why usefulness is so important.
Pragmatists
may also say that philosophy should help us develop “fruitful
lives” or “meaningful lives”. This begs even more philosophical
questions. What kind of meaningful lives? What is it to have a
meaningful life? Why should we care at all about having a meaningful
life? And, more sceptically, one can't help but assume (as with
analytic philosophers earlier) that when a pragmatist talks about
developing a “meaningful life” he has something very
specific in
mind. (Such as, say, becoming “politically engaged” or even
religiously
engaged.)
Richard
Rorty - who's sometimes called a neopragmatist
- is even more explicit about the nature of his non-philosophical
ends. He explicitly states that philosophy should be a tool of the
philosopher's political, social and cultural goals, causes and
dreams. This position clearly needs a non-pragmatic philosophical
defence in order to stop it from being philosophically circular in
nature. Yet Rorty - being Rorty - would probably have denied that and
said something “ironic” or clever such as:
One's
philosophical commitments to specific political, social and cultural
goals is ultimately a mater of faith, not philosophy or reason.
So
when pragmatists - and even a few analytic philosophers - say that
philosophy should treat “real problems”, another philosopher can
simply ask: Why?
He can also ask: What,
exactly, is a “real problem”?
Even a commitment to “applied ethics” (which, presumably, tackles
real
problems)
can motivate such questions.
For
example, take the ultimate meta-ethical question: Why
be moral at all?
If a philosopher takes a position of amoralism or immoralism; then,
presumably, he wouldn't have much work to do in applied ethics or
ethics generally. Or perhaps he would. It's feasible that he could
take an amoral or immoral position on all ethical positions. Though
surely that would be hard work.
Philosophical
Naturalism
Philosophical
naturalism is certainly a metaphilosophical position in the simple
sense that it takes a position on how philosophy should be done.
Moreover, it says that there is indeed progress in philosophy if and
only if (to use a cliché from analytic philosophy) philosophy takes
strong account of science. Philosophical naturalists therefore
believe that philosophical problems are “tractable
through the methods of the empirical sciences”.
Thus if science progresses or can solve problems, then so too can
(naturalistic) philosophy.
Psychology
is such a science; at least according to Quine. In his Ontological
Relativity and Other Essays
(1977),
he wrote:
“The
stimulation of his sensory receptors is all the evidence anybody has
had to go on, ultimately, in arriving at his picture of the world.
Why not just see how this construction really proceeds? Why not
settle for psychology?”
There
are of course philosophical problems with philosophical naturalism
and not all these problems will be relevant to all debates on
metaphilosophy. The main problem is whether or not naturalistic
philosophy can completely forgo the normative (at least in
epistemology) and thus ever be entirely descriptive (if that ever was
- or could be - the case).
Some
naturalistic philosophers go one step further than Quine and other
naturalists by actually doing
science. One may therefore ask: If
they actually do science, then aren't they scientists?
How are these philosophers – called “experimentalists” by some
- still actually philosophers? What does it mean to say that
experimental philosophers do science?
Well,
some philosophical experimentalists actually do empirical tests.
Isn't this is simply one step on from Quine's subservience to
psychology? And, of course, psychology and cognitive science can tell
you, for example, how it is that people reason. Or, in Quine's case,
how it is that they take in “sensory stimulation” and what it is
they do with that information. Indeed one step further on from this
would be for such psychologists to see how physicists take in sensory
stimulation and then see what they do with that information.1
The
obvious question now is:
Why
should the collective
way
in which physicists take in information - and then make use of it -
be of interest to a philosopher?
If
physicists - according to Quine and other naturalists - tell us what
there is, then finding out how such physicists take in sensory
information - and then make use of that information - will be
relevant to what philosophers also do. If philosophers ignore all
this, then they'll be philosophising in the dark; and thus, perhaps,
they'll be relying on their intuitions (on which much has been
written).
*********************************************
Note
1
A
metaphilosopher - or simply a philosopher! - may comment on the
relation between intuitions and a
priori
theorising and reject both. As a consequence of this, he may well
make use of empirical research in his philosophical work. This may
therefore be seen as a metaphilosophical position in that if one
rejects a
priori theorising
and/or intuitions (or at least rejects one's reliance on them in
philosophy), then one most also reject the large chunks of analytic
philosophy which are said to use intuitions to get the philosophical
ball rolling – or indeed to do more than that. (Ontic
structural realists, for example,
take
a very strong
stance against philosophical intuitions and see them as being
basically irrelevant.) Again it can be asked if this is simply a
philosophical dispute, not an example of a metaphilosophical stance.
Would this rejection of intuitions be what's called “experimental
philosophy”?
Not necessarily, though it can be.
No comments:
Post a Comment