i) Introduction
ii) There
are No Perceptual Illusions
iii) Are
Icons Representations of a Deeper Reality?
iv) How
Hoffman Employs Evolutionary Biology/Theory
v) The
Zero Reality Theorem
vi) Conclusion
This
piece is primarily about how Professor
Donald Hoffman
ties theories and ideas from evolutionary biology (or at least from
cognitive
science's
use of evolutionary biology) to his philosophical
theory of conscious
realism.
In
very simple terms, one may have no major problem with what Hoffman
says about “perceptions” and how they've “been
shaped by evolution”.
(On this subject alone, none of Hoffman's positions are original;
except, perhaps, in terms of fine detail.) What many people may have
a problem with is how Hoffman ties all this evolutionary stuff
to his highly-speculative philosophical position of conscious
realism.
More relevantly, Hoffman argues that the
evolutionary facts entail
(or at least strongly imply) his conscious realism.
There
are no Perceptual Illusions
Firstly,
let me express the very radical nature of Professor
Donald Hoffman's
position.
A
good way of doing this is by stating a position that Hoffman does not
hold.
Hoffman
doesn't believe that we suffer from collective “illusions” about
– or of – reality. Why doesn't he believe that? He doesn't
believe that because that would mean that sometimes
we get reality right.
That is, the word “illusion” only has a purchase (or any meaning)
in the context of our sometimes (or many times) getting reality
right. But Hoffman claims that we never
get reality right. Therefore the notion of illusion
serves no purpose in Hoffman's philosophical account of what he calls
“perceptions”.
So
let's use Hoffman's own
words
here:
“This
standard theory of illusions clearly cannot be endorsed by ITP [the
Interface Theory of Perception], because ITP says that none of our
perceptions are veridical.. [Thus] [i]t would be unhelpful for ITP to
say that all perceptions are illusory.”
Are
Icons Representations of a Deeper Reality?
So
let's forget (for a moment) about illusions or getting reality right
or wrong.
Hoffman
argues that instead of our “representations” being “accurate”
(or inaccurate): they are, in fact, simply “adaptive
guides to behavior”.
One
may now wonder why Hoffman accepts the word “representation”
in the first place. After all, if we systematically get
the world wrong,
then what justification has Hoffman got for using the word
“representation” at all?
Hoffman's
answer to this is simple.
In
Hoffman's scheme, we simply have representations of what he calls
“icons”.
However, it can now be said that not many – or even any –
philosophers or laypersons have ever used the word “representations”
to mean representations-of-icons.
But that won't concern Hoffman. After all, he will no doubt say that
it doesn't matter what philosophers and laypersons take
representations to be: it's what representations actually are that
matters. And, in Hoffman's philosophical
scheme, representations represent
icons, not reality (or the world).
The
following is Hoffman's own analogy of what he takes that deeper
reality (to
use those two words ironically)
to be. (In fact he uses the words “deeper reality” himself.) He
writes:
“[C]onsider
what you see when you look into a mirror. All you see is skin, hair,
eyes, lips. But as you stand there, looking at yourself, you know
first hand that the face you see in the mirror shows little of who
you really are. It does not show your hopes, fears, beliefs, or
desires. It does not show your consciousness. It does not show that
you are suffering a migraine or savoring a melody. All you see, and
all that the user interfaces of others can see, is literally skin
deep. Other people see a face, not the conscious agent that is your
deeper reality.”
There's
a further problem here.
In
Hoffman's scheme, icons themselves are representations. That is,
Hoffman's icons reflect (or stand in for) a/the
deeper reality.
However, if that's the case, then we must have representations
of representations.
That is, our representations are representations
of icons;
which are, in turn, representations
of a deeper reality.
(Alternatively and less grandly,
icons are representations of things which aren't themselves
representations.)
How
Hoffman Employs Evolutionary Theory/Biology
Hoffman
seems to be using evolutionary
theory
(as he does with talk of “mathematical
models”)
in order to sell us a speculative philosophy (i.e., conscious
realism)
that's not actually directly connected to (that) evolutionary
theory/biology at all. Sure, Hoffman attempts to connect it in the
sense that the/his evolutionary stance on perceptions
shows us that accurate (or “truthful”,
as Hoffman puts it) perceptions of reality are a bad thing. But
that's an evolutionary point about survival. It doesn't show us that
metaphysical - or even naïve - realism is false. It shows us
precisely what
it says on the tin:
accurate/truthful perceptions of the world may not (or do
not)
help us survive as a species.
So
all the technical detail that Hoffman offers us about this particular
evolutionary theory doesn't back up his conscious
realism;
even though he believes that it does so. This means that the
following
passage,
for
example, is
either almost irrelevant to Hoffman's philosophical
thesis or he's simply dropping mathematical and scientific names in order to back of that thesis.
He
states:
“When
you analyze the equations of evolutionary game theory it turns out
that, whenever an organism that sees reality as it is competes with
an organism that sees none of reality and is tuned to fitness, the
organism that sees reality as it is goes extinct.”
So
let's quote Hoffman again. He
states:
“The
classic argument is that those of our ancestors who saw more
accurately had a competitive advantage over those who saw less
accurately and thus were more likely to pass on their genes that
coded for those more accurate perceptions, so after thousands of
generations we can be quite confident that we’re the offspring of
those who saw accurately, and so we see accurately.”
Hoffman
claims that this is the standard picture. He then continues:
“That
sounds very plausible. But I think it is utterly false. It
misunderstands the fundamental fact about evolution, which is that
it’s about fitness
functions
— mathematical functions that describe how well a given strategy
achieves the goals of survival and reproduction. The mathematical
physicist Chetan Prakash proved a theorem
that I devised that says: According to evolution by natural
selection, an organism that sees reality as it is will never be more
fit than an organism of equal complexity that sees none of reality
but is just tuned to fitness. Never.”
The
main argument which follows is that Hoffman assumes the existence of
a “reality” (or a “real world”) at precisely the moment that
he's at pains to reject it.
For
example, in the passage just quoted above, Hoffman puts his foot in
it by using the phrase “whenever an organism [] sees reality as it
is”, then this
or that
happens to it. So, again, is Hoffman accepting that there is a
reality
as it is?
No? Yes? Sure, he's also saying that seeing reality as
it is
has been disadvantageous from an evolutionary point of view. But what
has that to do with reality
as it is?
More relevantly, if our ancestors saw reality as
it is
(and subsequently died out), then surely that must work against
Hoffman's consciousness realism in which there is no
reality as it is.
All we have, instead, are
the contents of minds (or “infinite
consciousnesses”)
and the subsequent interactions of what he calls “conscious
agents”.
Anti-realists
also argue that we don't see reality as
it is.
But that's not the point: Hoffman does and does not believe that
there's a reality as
it is.
He believes that there is a reality
as
it is
when he discusses evolutionary theory/biology (i.e., when discussing
our ancestors). And he doesn't believe there is a reality as
it is
when it comes to his philosophical
position of conscious realism.
To
repeat: Hoffman states
that “our
ancestors who saw reality accurately”
died out. Nonetheless, Hoffman is still conceding that reality was
seen
accurately
– if by those ancestors who were deselected by evolution. This
means that Hoffman believed that there was both a reality and a
reality which was seen accurately. The problem, according to Hoffman,
is that seeing the world accurately was disadvantageous for those
ancestors. However, even if that was indeed the case; it still works
against Hoffman's conscious
realism and
possibly in favour of some kind of metaphysical
realism,
anti-realism
or
even
naïve
realism.
Of course Hoffman can happily accept that these dead species did see
reality either in full or in part. So there was indeed a reality to
see. It's simply the case that human beings today
don't see reality in full – or even in part! This leads us to the
possibility that there may be organisms or creatures around today
that see reality better than we do! Of course these creatures, in
turn, will be deselected (i.e., if Hoffman's thesis is correct). That is,
evolution is an ongoing process and that must mean that some/many
organisms around today do indeed perceive reality in some shape or
form – better than human beings do. It's just that they'll
eventually be deselected according to the laws of evolution.
But
this isn't quite right!
According
to Hoffman's conscious
realism,
no
organism
or creature could ever have perceived reality. That's because
Hoffman's philosophical
thesis has it that all there is to reality is what goes in the heads
(which are also “icons”) of cognitive
agents
- whether rudimentary cognitive agents (say, snails or cats) or
sophisticated conscious agents (whether apes or human beings).
So
Hoffman can't have it both ways.
He
can't stress a consciousness-based philosophy at the same time as
admitting that previous species might have got reality right. If
conscious realism (which I see as a
kind of
idealism) is correct, then no
species
has ever got reality right. All they might have got right is the
contents of their own consciousnesses or minds.
Of
course the way of of this problem is simply to argue that reality
simply
is what
we discover (as it were) either in our own consciousness or in
collective consciousnesses – and that seems to be what Hoffman
hints at.
Thus certain creatures (or organisms) dying out is utterly beside the
point when it comes to Hoffman's philosophical position – conscious
realism.
Hoffman
also cites what he calls an “objection” to his position which is
useful for the positions expressed in this piece.
He
writes:
“The
question of whether our perceptions are truthful is irrelevant to
scientific theories of perception. Those theories aim to understand
the internal principles of a biological system.”
So
let's rewrite the quote above in this way:
The
question of whether our perceptions are truthful - in all
evolutionary accounts of perception - is irrelevant to all
philosophical/ontological theories of reality. Philosophical theories
aim to understand reality regardless of our past - or present -
evolutionary shortcomings.
Of
course the obvious answer to the above is to claim that we simply
can't override (or overcome) our evolutionary shortcomings when it
comes to our perceptions of what we take reality (or the world) to
be. But this is clearly false. Homo sapiens have overrode
(or overcome) many of their evolutionary shortcomings in human
history.
For
example, our brains weren't designed to do higher maths and board
games; though we do higher maths and board games. Similarly, we
weren't designed by evolution to keep pets; though we do keep pets.
So, in the case of our perceptions, we can
override (or overcome) our evolution-caused
shortcomings too. Indeed we have
done so. More relevantly, we may also override (or overcome) our
evolutionary shortcomings when it comes to what we take reality to
actually be.
The
Zero Reality Theorem
The
subheading 'The Zero Reality Theorem' above is meant to be ironic in
that Hoffman himself often uses the pretentious and highfalutin word
“theorem” (at least that's what it is when used outside of
mathematics and logic) for many of his positions. Indeed in this
context he calls his position The
Fitness Beats Truth Theorem
(the FBT Theorem). And that usage needs to be quickly commented upon.
Put
simply, a mathematical
theorem
can be proved from a given set of axioms or premises. A scientific
theory, on the other hand, cannot be proved and is often also taken
to be falsifiable. (The importance and accuracy
of falsifiability in science has been questioned; especially by
philosophers.)
Now why is Hoffman using the word “theorem” for his scientific
and philosophical positions? Is he stating (or implying) that they've
literally been proved? Yes he is: Hoffman himself claims that
his theorems have been proved (i.e., by Dr.
Chetan Prakash
at the Department of Mathematics, California State University). At
least the mathematical parts have. However, there's much more than
mathematics to Hoffman's various theorems
(actually, theories).
There's the philosophical speculations and the physical science, for
a start.
Hoffman
makes another mistake when he
states:
“It’s
very clear. If our senses evolved and were shaped by natural
selection, the probability that we see reality as it is is zero.”
The
final clause
“the
probability that we see reality as it is is zero”
doesn't
follow from the first clause:
“If
our senses evolved and were shaped by natural selection...”
That
is, the final clause doesn't follow unless one already
accepts
Hoffman's many philosophical assumptions and arguments.
For
a start, not seeing reality completely
as it is
isn't
the same thing as seeing “zero” (Hoffman's word) of reality.
Evolution might have designed us to see only limited aspects of
reality. And that's an old argument.
For
example, many philosophers have argued that a “Kantian
manifold”
(as it were) couldn't
be registered by a human brain or by human consciousness. And that's
because there's simply too much information or data to take in.
However, that doesn't mean that we have zero
knowledge of reality or the world.
This
is also to ignore the phrase “seeing reality as it is” and what
that actually means. One needn't be a metaphysical realist or a naïve
realist in order to reject Hoffman's conscious realism; which is, effectively, a
collective/pluralist/personalist/etc.
idealism.
That is, we can't quickly move from our not getting reality in
toto
to not getting anything
of reality at all. And it's that possibility of not getting anything
at all which has led to Hoffman to embrace his own conscious realism.
Yet that's like stopping eating food simply because one became sick
after eating a single mouldy apple.
Conclusion
The
final question is this:
Does
Hoffman successfully tie his evolutionary account of perceptions to
his conscious realism?
More
clearly, can we move from our ancestors getting
reality wrong
and therefore surviving, to our getting reality
wrong
today? Possibly. However, as already stated, Hoffman seems to concede
the following:
i)
Some of our ancestors did get reality right.
ii)
They didn't survive.
iii)
Therefore there was a reality as it is
- at least for them.
Now
one can agree here and say that all those creatures which saw reality
accurately died out. The point is whether or not Hoffman's
evolutionary detail backs up - or even entails - his conscious realism. Yes, the long jump from evolutionary theory/biology
to Hoffman's conscious realism (or, more simply, to philosophy)
is very speculative indeed.
No comments:
Post a Comment