These pieces are primarily commentaries on the 'Ontic Structural Realism and the Philosophy of Physics' chapter of James Ladyman and Don Ross's book Every Thing Must Go. There are also a handful of references to – and quotes from – other parts of that book.
********************************************
Ladyman
and Ross (L & R) refer to Kant a few times in Every
Thing Must Go.
Strangely enough, one time they do so is in response to the various
philosophers who've seen “strong affinities” between their own
work and Kant's. Nonetheless, L & R tell us “how [their]
general account differs from that of Kant”. That fundamental
difference is also the main purpose of this short piece.
Every Noumenon Must Go
We
can go back to John Locke to see that it may be permanently
impossible for us to ascertain the true nature of objects or things (i.e., his
“something, I know not what”). In An
Essay
Concerning Human Understanding,
Locke writes:
“…it
is impossible for us to know, that this or that quality or Idea has a
necessary connexion with a real Essence, of which we have no Idea at
all, whatever Species that supposed real Essence may be imagined to
constitute.”
[IV.vi.5]
That's
also partly why Bishop Berkeley turned towards empirical idealism and
away from scientific materialism and the scepticism it engendered. In
his Three
Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous,
Berkeley wrote:
“....
the whole issue can be allowed to rest on a single question: is it
possible to conceive of a sensible object existing independently of
any perceiver? The challenge seems easy enough at first. All I have
to do is think of something so remote—a tree in the middle of the
forest, perhaps—that no one presently has it in mind. But if I
conceive of this thing, then it is present in my mind as I think of
it, so it is not truly independent of all perception.”
[Dialogue 1]
Thus
Kant brought noumena into the debate. Again, the problem of noumena
caused various philosophers to embrace (Kantian) transcendental
idealism once again – and so did many 19th-century scientists (e.g., Mach,
Helmholtz, Boltzmann, Hertz, early Einstein, etc.).
If
we come up to date, L & R quote Frank Jackson saying that “we
know next to nothing about the intrinsic nature of the world”.
Indeed we “know only its causal cum relational nature”.
One
way out of this impasse (of noumena and the consequent embracing of
idealism) is to become some kind of structuralist. Thus L & R
cites Peter Unger arguing that “our knowledge of the world is
purely structural”. What's more, Peter Unger also argues that
“things
in themselves [i.e., noumena]... are idle wheels in metaphysics and
the PPC imposes a moratorium on such purely speculative philosophical
toys”.
Kantianism
A
semi-Kantian position (needlessly Kantian, according to L & R) is
also offered by Mauro Dorato (as quoted by L & R). Dorato writes:
“the
concept of unobservable entities that are involved in the structural
relations always has some conventional element, and the reality of
the entities is constituted by, or derived from, more and more
relations in which they are involved.”
I
wrote semi-Kantian because that passage begins in a Kantian
manner and ends with a structuralism of some kind. The Kantian bit is the following clause:
“...
the concept of unobservable entities that are involved in the
structural relations always has some conventional element.”
However,
the passage ends with these words:
“...
the reality of the entities is constituted by, or derived from, more
and more relations in which they are involved.”
L
& R would simply say: Get rid of these “unobservable
entities”. After all, from what Dorato has said it can be
concluded that all we've really got are relations and structure. Or
in more detail:
Relations
don't constitute entities and neither are entities derived from
relations. Relations constitute (more) relations and (more) relations
are derived from prior relations. It's relations all the way down
folks.
To
be crude, it can be said that Ladyman and Ross believe that all
non-structural realists are to some extent Kantians. Or, at the
least, they make the same Kantian mistake.
L
& R specifically pick out what they call the “epistemic
structural realist” as a Kantian (or quasi-Kantian).
So
why 'Kantian'? L & R write:
“...
an epistemic structural realist may insist in a Kantian spirit...
there being such objects is a necessary condition for our empirical
knowledge of the world.”
This
is a good description of the noumenal grounding of Kant's metaphysics
and indeed his epistemology. You can sum it up with a simple Kantian
question:
If
there are no noumenal objects (which ground our representations, etc.), then what's it all about?
Even
if our representations, models, "posited objects", etc. don't somehow
mirror - or simply represent - objects (or if we didn't have the
noumenal grounding in the first place), then surely we have precisely
nothing. Or as L & R put it (almost quoting Kant word-for-word):
“...there
being such objects is a necessary condition for our empirical
knowledge of the world.”
So,
again, we may not mirror nature or objects; though we must capture
something. Then again, how can we represent - let alone mirror - something as strange as Kantian noumena? How would that work?
This
is when L & R say: Yes, we capture structure. That
won't quite work because the Kantians and quasi-Kantians think
they're capturing (if not mirroring) determinate objects. L & R
clearly don't think that. That's why L & R appear to make what
can be seen as the obvious conclusion. They write:
“....
we shall argue that in the light of contemporary physics... that talk
of unknowable intrinsic natures and individuals is idle and has no
justified place in metaphysics. This is the sense in which our view
is eliminative...”
One
can conclude, after reading L & R, that because we can't get at
objects in their pristine metaphysically-realist state (we can't
mirror objects), then, if that's a necessary truth, we may as well say
that “structure is all there is”. This ties in nicely with L &
R's position in which Kantian noumena may as well drop out of the
picture (as was the case, to some extent, with Bishop Berkeley). Or,
as Wittgenstein once put it
(though about something else), an object or noumenon
is “a wheel that can be turned though nothing else moves with it is
not part of the mechanism”[§271].
To
put the case very simply, there are two positions which one can adopt
here:
i) There are objects (or noumena), though we can never access them as they are “in themselves”.
ii) If we can't access objects as they are in themselves, then why not drop such objects completely from the picture?
It
can be said that ii) follows from i); though it
can't be said, strictly speaking, to follow logically from i).
References
Berkeley,
George. (1713)Three
Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous
Kant,
Emmanuel. (1787)
Critique
of Pure Reason
Ladyman, James, Ross, Don. (2007) Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalised
Lock, John. (1690) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
No comments:
Post a Comment