“… the role of the general term is to identify the referents – not to identify the ‘kind of identity’ asserted.” (John Perry, 1970)
“A bare knowledge of the reference of the name a will consist…in knowing, of some object, that a refers to it, where this is a complete characterisation of this particular piece of knowledge.” [Dummett, 1991]
“…there cannot be a proper name whose whole sense consists in its having a certain object as referent, without the sense determining that object as referent in some particular way.” [Dummett, 1973]
Can
we have basic naming (or the “identification of referents”)
without the latter kind of identification? What is at the ostended
point? Doesn’t individuation (therefore sometimes the
identification of kinds) come before the basic kind of Kripkean
naming and identification? Wouldn't this be an epistemological
question, rather than an ontological one? It would be a question
about our knowledge of an object, rather than (the reality) of the
object. It may still be the case (in conformity with Kripke) that we
can only know an object to be the object it is through its
ontological essence. Here again we see a philosopher making the same
distinction:
“Kripke did make a feasible distinction between a description giving the content of a name and merely fixing its referent.” [Jason Stanley, 1997]
“the causal theory of names elaborated by Kripke and others. Proper names, unlike definite descriptions, can be used by speakers to refer to objects without mediation of ‘concepts’ or descriptive clusters. They can be used to capture and institutionalise an act of ostension.” [Marcus, 1978]
The
traditional problem was that if referents depended on concepts (or
‘descriptive clusters’), then each person would bring along his
own concepts (or descriptive clusters). It was supposed to follow
from this that a reference couldn't rely on a single concept or a
single descriptive cluster. The referent would therefore be lost
amongst rival - or simply different - conceptual contents of names.
Why
was it thought that if the reference couldn't rely on specific
concepts that it could escape all concepts? Everyone would still be
having causal contact with the same referent [see Donald Davidson,
1989]; though that causal contact alone wouldn't tell us which
concepts or descriptions were the correct ones (if there are correct
ones). If everyone were still having the same causal contact with the
same object (or the same spatial region or physical mass), then that
wouldn't matter. Different or even contradictory concepts would still
be related to the same object or spatial region/physical mass.
Thus,
in an indirect sense admittedly, acts of ostension could still be
‘institutionalised’ [Marcus, 1978]; thought we couldn't guarantee
uniformity of conceptual choices. The object wouldn't be lost; though
the guaranteed uniformity of concept choices would be. And, of
course, if different people brought the same conceptual baggage with
them, then that in itself would/could generate a certain degree of
conceptual uniformity. However, that wouldn't be guaranteed. And it
could be possible to generate agreement between different or
contradictory concepts if the concepts of the object or spatial
region referred back to the object as it is “standardly recognised”
[Paul Moser, 1993]. Of course what is standardly recognised
would still be a contingent matter. Even the standard conceptual
description of the object would still not be the way the object
describes itself. Therefore there's no reason to suppose that what is
standard today will be standard next week.
No comments:
Post a Comment