i) Introduction
ii) Objective
Truth?
iii) Philosophy
Must Be Political?
iv) Richard
Rorty
The
term 'post-analytic
philosophy'
was first used in the mid-1980s. At that time it referred to those
philosophers who were indebted to analytic philosophy, but who, nonetheless, believed that they'd moved on from it (for whatever
reasons).
The
term seems, prima
facie,
odd. After all, how can philosophers be 'post'- or anti-analysis?
Surely even most examples of post-analytic philosophy will contain
analyses of sorts. (This isn't necessarily to say that philosophy
must consist entirely
of analysis.)
Thus, the term must instead refer to the tradition
(in a broad sense) of analytic philosophy. But which aspects of that
tradition? Which particular philosophers? Did all analytic
philosophers have an philosophical essence in common? And let's not
forget that philosophical analysis occurred well before the analytic
tradition got under way. (What is it that Hume, Hobbes, Aquinas, etc.
did if it wasn't - at least in part - analysis?)
The
above are all problems which, to some extent, subside
once the history and use of the term 'post-analytic philosophy' is
studied.
However,
it is indeed analysis that some philosophers seem to have a problem
with. Or, rather, perhaps it's more accurate to say 'philosophical
analysis' rather than the simple 'analysis'. This is obviously the
case because the words 'philosophical analysis' are more particular
than 'analysis' and it may/will contain assumptions as to what
philosophical
analysis actually
is.
Objective
Truth?
If
we want to put meat on what post-analytic philosophers see to be the
problem (or simply a problem) with analytic philosophy, it's best to
consult late-20th century and contemporary American
pragmatism.
This school is itself seen as being part of the post-analytic
movement (i.e., which isn't a determinate or real school).
Many
would say that such American pragmatists
have a problem with the very notion of objective truth, realism and
representationalism. They are things they see as being an idée
fixe
throughout the history of philosophy. And this, indeed, is no less
the case when it came to 20th-century analytic philosophy.
A
personal objection to this is that I've hardly read a single analytic
philosopher mention - or use - the words “objective truth”. (I
have read, however, Peter
van Inwagen's
'Objectivity'.)
Then again, it can easily be countered that a philosopher needn't use
the actual words “objective truth” in order for him to be
committed to the notion of objective
truth.
In other words, perhaps he simply calls it by another name.1
In
any case, the position that objective truth doesn't exist (or that
it's not a worthy aim in philosophy) goes alongside a stress on the
contingency of cognitive activity, the importance of convention and
utility, and, indeed, the idea that human (or social) progress can
never be ignored – not even in philosophy. Nonetheless, here again
I don't see how there's an automatic (or prior) problem with accepting
all this and still engaging in analytic philosophy (or in
philosophical analysis).
For
example and in very basic terms, one could offer a philosophical
analysis of philosophical
analysis
(or some part thereof). And then, as a result, see philosophical
problems with such philosophical analysis. Despite that, such a
philosopher would still be in the domain of analytic philosophy (or
of philosophical analysis).
Strangely
enough, Richard
Rorty
seems to agree with this position. Or, at the least, he says
something similar. In an interview conducted by Wayne Hudson and Win
van Reijen,
Rorty states:
"I
think that analytic philosophy can keep its highly professional
methods, the insistence on detail and mechanics, and just drop its
transcendental
project.
I'm not out to criticize analytic philosophy as a style. It's a good
style. I think the years of superprofessionalism were beneficial."
I
said the position is “similar” to the one advanced by Rorty. It's
similar in the sense that an analytic philosopher needn't “drop
[his] transcendental project”. That is, an analytic philosopher may
be fully aware of Rorty's positions/arguments (or the general
positions of post-analytic philosophers) and still be committed to
the transcendental project. (Of course we'd need to know what Rorty
means by the words “transcendental
project”.)
Philosophy
Must be Political?
It
seems that the position of many post-analytic philosophers is
primarily political - or at least primarily social – in nature.
Hilary
Putnam
(1985), for example, has said that analytic philosophy has “come
to the end of its own project—the dead end”.
That can be taken to mean that philosophy should connect itself more
thoroughly with other academic disciplines. Or, more broadly, that
analytic philosophy should connect itself with culture or society as
a whole.
The
problem is that, on and off, analytic philosophy has already
connected itself to many other disciplines. (Admittedly, that's been
more the case since the 1980s and the rise of cognitive science.) To
give just a couple of examples: the logical
positivists
connected themselves to science (or at least to physics). And, to
give another example, philosophers in the 19th century connected
themselves to logic, mathematics and, again, to science. This
non-ostentatious “interdisciplinary”
nature of philosophy has been the case, in fact, throughout the
history of philosophy.
One
can also say that philosophy can connect itself to other disciplines
- and even culture as a whole - and still remain analytic philosophy.
Philosophers can still practice philosophical analysis. (This, again,
raises the question as to what analytic philosophy - or philosophical
analysis - actually is.)
A
philosopher may also ask
why he
should connect himself to other disciplines - never mind to something
as vague (or as broad) as culture.
In other words, a philosopher must have philosophical reasons as to
why this would be a good thing, just as a philosopher must have
philosophical reasons as to why it's a bad thing. That means that
there'll be philosophical angles to this very debate. However, it can
be added, those angles needn't always be philosophical in nature.
Another
slant on this philosophy-society "binary
opposition"
is that it is argued that analytic philosophy is too professional and
therefore too narrow. In other words, analytic philosophers are
over-concerned with very tiny, narrow and specialised problems which
have almost zero connection to society as a whole or indeed to
anything else.
More
technically and philosophically, it can also be argued that certain
central commitments and assumptions of analytic philosophy have been
shown to be indefensible. (Hence Putnam's own words quoted earlier.)
Yet
all disciplines can be said to concerned with narrow or specialised
issues or concerns. Yet this is an accusation more often aimed at analytic philosophy than at any other academic subject.
Richard
Rorty
Richard
Rorty appears
to be talking about analytic philosophy as it was in the past (say,
the 1950s to the 1970s), not as it is today or as it has been since,
say, the 1980s.
Take
the view that analytic philosophy has as its primary aim a
form of knowledge which grounds all other forms of knowledge.
This is odd. It's true that much traditional philosophy has placed
various philosophical domains in the position of what used to be
called First
Philosophy.
(It was once metaphysics, then epistemology, then philosophy of language, then philosophy of mind...) However, in the 20th century this has been far from the
case. Indeed philosophers - throughout the 20th century - have argued
against the nature of a first
philosophy.
Take
naturalists
(e.g., the logical positivists, then Quine): arguably, they placed
science (or simply physics) in the role of first
philosophy.
(Although such naturalists saw physics as being primary, that isn't
in itself a commitment to also seeing it as some kind of first
philosophy.)
It
must be said that just as Rorty's post-philosophy is a philosophical
position, so too is the Wittgensteinian
attempt to “dissolve” and then disregard philosophical problems
(if not philosophy itself). This position can be said to be held by
Putnam and John
McDowell,
as well as by Rorty. (A more specific example of this would be the
“problem” of how mind and language are connected to the world.)2
In
any case, there's just as strong case for arguing that Rorty's later
position was more a case of post-philosophy
than post-analytic
philosophy.
In other words, like Heidegger
and
Derrida,
Rorty had a problem with the whole damn show that is Western philosophy. And,
here again, it can be argued that Rorty's position was more political
(or social) than strictly philosophical. That said, a
position that rejects philosophy in
toto
can't help being philosophical – in some or many ways – itself, as Rorty would have no doubt happily admitted. (Jacques Derrida did
admit this.)
Notes
1) If you say that an argument (or a single statement) is
“warranted
and therefore assertible”,
then is that a case of being wedded to the notion of objective truth?
Or is the notion of warranted
assertibility
a different species entirely?
2)
I put the word “problem” in scare quotes because the very stance
of seeing such problems as problems
means - according to Rorty, Derrida, Heidegger, etc. - that we've
fallen prey to particular philosophical “style
of thinking”. However, that position too would be a philosophical position.
No comments:
Post a Comment