As
a non-scientist, I've often little idea if statements or arguments about quantum mechanics and its influence on the brain and
consciousness are true. I sometimes understand what's
being said. However, that understanding alone doesn't in and of itself tell
me whether or not what's being said is true (or correct). A scientist may tell me that p
is true or correct; though is that enough?
Perhaps
I should have faith
in the science instead. The problem is, faith in which
scientific theory and in
which
scientists? And what are the “criteria
of theory-choice”
for the layperson; never mind for the scientist?
*************************************
Roger
Penrose's New Physics?
We
can ask if the new physics which Roger Penrose demands - for a science of consciousness - is physics at
all. It's of course the case that physics has often taken off in
radically new directions. Nonetheless, that doesn't mean that every
radically new direction is to be accepted or will prove to be
successful or productive. And it doesn't mean that every new
direction will remain securely in the domain of physics.
So what's the nature of Penrose's new physics?
Take
one example: Penrose's position that the very-small scale and the
large scale may be physically connected. Traditionally it was thought
that what applied to the very-small scale doesn't apply to the large
or very-large scale. What's more, it is primarily quantum
gravity that accounts for this phenomenon.
How
does this apply to the brain and consciousness?
The
quantum happenings in the microtubules (the very-small scale) are said to affect the brain as a whole (the large scale) and thus be responsible
for consciousness. Again, it's quantum gravity that connects these
quantum happenings in the microtubules within the brain as a whole.
Yet
it's often said - often by philosophers - that quantum happenings in
the brain have negligible effect on the brain as a whole. As a
consequence, critics conclude that quantum happenings in the
microtubules can't be the source of consciousness. However, quantum
happenings do indeed have an effect on the large scale; as Penrose
himself makes plain here:
“The
very existence of solid bodies, the strengths and physical properties
of materials, the nature of chemistry, the colours of substances, the
phenomena of freezing and boiling, the reliability of inheritance —
these, and many other familiar properties, require the quantum theory
for their explanations.”
True,
these “solid bodies”, etc. may “require the quantum theory for
their explanations”; though that doesn't automatically mean that
they have effects which can be observed or which are in any way
substantive. Thus all this doesn't also mean that the impact of quantum
mechanics on the macro-world is important or even mildly important.
It simply means that quantum mechanics is a part of the whole
picture. So, in the sense of
supplying a complete picture - then, yes, of course quantum theory
will be required. However, this question still remains:
In what precise ways do quantum happenings effect macro-objects, macro-events and macro-conditions?
Despite
this (possibly) quasi/neo-Kantian
or quasi/neo-phenomenalist account of the nature of quantum
happenings on Penrose's cricket balls, the point may still be missed.
(Penrose
himself
mentions
the lack of quantum-mechanical effects on cricket balls.)
In
any case, as a possible consequence of quantum-mechanical effects on
macro-objects, macro-events and macro-conditions, Penrose finishes
off by saying something that was - perhaps - spurring him on all
along. Thus:
“Perhaps,
also, the phenomenon of consciousness is something that cannot be
understood in entirely classical terms. Perhaps our minds are
qualities rooted in some strange and wonderful feature of those
physical laws which actually govern the world we inhabit... Perhaps,
in some sense, this is ‘why’ we, as sentient beings, must live in
a quantum world, rather than an entirely classical one... Might a
quantum world be required so that thinking, perceiving creatures,
such as ourselves, can be constructed from its substance?”
Again, the
question remains:
Is
it the case that microtubules, quantum gravity and quantum mechanics
provide the answers to all Penrose's questions about consciousness?
Quantum
Gravity
Roger
Penrose puts his position on quantum gravity and quantum
mechanics in the following way:
“This
change is to play its role when quantum mechanics becomes
appropriately united with general relativity, i.e. in the sought-for
theory of quantum gravity. Most physicists do not believe that
quantum theory needs to change when it is united with general
relativity.”
More
relevantly to our discussion, Penrose was and is still is deeply
aware – and evidently so - of the arguments against his position as
it's applied to the brain and consciousness. Indeed when he wrote The
Emperor's New Mind in
1990,
he
didn't have a position on microtubules. (Microtubules aren't
mentioned in this well-known book.) Even neurons and
neurotransmitters only get
four
mentions.
This
is what Penrose also had to say about the opposition's position on
the brain and quantum mechanics:
“...
they would argue that on a scale relevant to our brains the physical
effects of any quantum gravity must be totally insignificant! They
would say (very reasonably) that although such physical effects might
indeed be important at the absurdly tiny distance scale known as the
Planck length — which is
10
35 m, some 100000000000000000000 times smaller than the size of the
tiniest subatomic particle — these effects should have no direct
relevance whatever to phenomena at the far far larger ‘ordinary’
scales of, say, down only to 10
12 m,
where the chemical or electrical processes that are important to
brain activity hold sway.”
Indeed
Penrose went further by saying that his detractors would say that not
even ordinary
gravity (as it were) could affect the brain. Thus:
“Indeed,
even classical (i.e. non-quantum) gravity has almost no influence on
these electrical and chemical activities.”
Penrose
concludes with the following sceptical words (as offered by his
opponents):
“If
classical gravity is of no consequence, then how on earth could any
tiny ‘quantum correction’ to the classical theory make any
difference at all? Moreover, since deviations from quantum theory
have never been observed, it would seem to be even more unreasonable
to imagine that any tiny putative deviation from standard quantum
theory could have any conceivable role to play in mental phenomena!”
In
the above, Penrose placed
his
cards down on the table when he said that “deviations from
quantum theory have never been observed”. (Though the word
“observed” may be controversial here.) Nonetheless, this is the
crux of Penrose's position:
i)
Quantum
gravity (or the “structure of space-time”) may have an impact on
quantum mechanics.
ii)
Therefore quantum gravity may affect the nature of the brain
and consciousness.
All
the above is expressed in the following:
“..
I am not concerned so much with the effects that quantum mechanics
might have on our theory (Einstein’s general relativity) of the
structure of space-time, but with the reverse: namely the effects
that Einstein’s space-time theory might have on the very structure
of quantum mechanics.”
This
is, of course, “an unconventional view-point” (or it was in
1990!). It's “unconventional that general relativity should have
any influence at all on the structure of quantum mechanics!”. More
basically, Penrose believed that “the problems within quantum
theory itself are of a fundamental character”.
Penrose
concluded – again, in 1990 (27 years ago) - by saying that “any
putative quantum gravity theory would surely be very remote from the
phenomena governing the behaviour of brains”.
Quantum
Gravity and Microtubules
At
its most basic, gravitation and general
relativity aren't
integrated in quantum theory. That alone makes Penrose's views on
consciousness speculative. Penrose himself says that quantum theory
doesn't play a part in (his) “objective
state reduction”.
It's here where quantum-gravitational effects come to the rescue –
at least as far as Penrose is concerned.
Why
the pressing need to square (or couple) gravity with quantum
mechanics? Some argue that that a classical system can't be squared
(or coupled) with a quantum system. (Though that would of course
depend on what the word “coupling” or “squaring” means.)
So
why does Penrose see his position on quantum gravity as important in
relation to brains and their microtubules? According to Penrose, it's
in the microtubules where quantum states can become “reduced” by
gravitational influence. This isn't the case with the large-scale
brain as a whole – the “classical environment”. Or at least
with the brain as a whole (or its parts) taken as also being
large-scale.
What's
happening here is a strange a connection between the very-small scale
and the large scale. In Penrose's view, the brain (or its
microtubules) are linked to fundamental spacetime geometry and thus
also to quantum gravity.
Max
Tegmark
(1999/2000),
among many others, has questioned not only the relevance of quantum
states in the brain as a whole (or in the brain's separate parts);
but also in the case of the very small microtubules. Put simply, quantum
happenings can't last long enough to have an important role in
consciousness. (The consensus seems to be on Tegmark's side on this; rather
than on Penrose's.)
More
technically and in terms of quantum happenings, Tegmark believes that
even in the microtubules (never mind the brain or its other
large-scale parts), quantum superpositions within the microtubuli
would - or could - never last long enough to bring about
consciousness (or any other significant mental phenomena).
Nonetheless, Tegmark's position has in turn - rather predictably -
been the subject of criticism.
S.
Hagan
and Stuart Hameroff (2002),
for example, have backed up the position of Penrose by saying that
such quantum superpositions could (or can) last long enough to have
significant large-scale effects – at least in theory. Indeed
there's been substantive research – i.e., outside
the brain and consciousness - into interacting spins and entanglement
which suggests that superpositions can have a longer lifespan.
The
connections between the very-small scale and the large scale have
just been stressed. Confusingly, this phenomenon runs parallel with
the need for quantum happenings within “systems” to remain
isolated from the outside of the aforesaid systems. More specifically
(in terms of the brain and consciousness), Hameroff and Penrose do
believe that microtubules are isolated from the rest of the brain.
Due to the spiral structure and shape of microtubules, the quantum
happenings within them remain isolated from the outside world (i.e., from the rest of the brain and outside the brain itself). However, if this is the
case, how is the quantum very-small scale connected to the brain's
large scale? According to Penrose, it's quantum gravity which links
the quantum happenings in the microtubules with the brain to bring
about consciousness.
These
supposed connections between the very-small scale and the large scale
are part of the problem.
In
detail, the philosophers Rick Grush
and Patricia Churchland
have argued that
microtubules can't pass on their quantum happenings to each
other
(or from one neuron to another). That would be needed, for example,
in order to explain “the unity of consciousness”. More
concretely, how are the quantum happenings in the microtubules (the
very-small-scale happenings) passed onto the large-scale happenings
in neurons, neurotransmitters
and neuromodulators?
To
bring this grand theorising down to earth, let's cite one of Penrose
and Hameroff's own
examples
of this.
Hameroff once believed that when
a subject is rendered unconsciousness by anaesthetics, that the subject's microtubules were
responsible for this. As a consequence, Hameroff made a strong
connection between these microtubules and consciousness. In other words, if
microtubules can turn consciousness off;
then surely they can (or must) also turn consciousness on.
The problem is that this specific theory about anaesthesia was shown
to be false. Microtubules don't cause unconsciousness.
More
specifically on anaesthetics. It's agreed that in certain cases of
anaesthetically-induced unconsciousness the microtubules are
involved. However, this isn't true in all cases. Indeed anaesthetics
can bring about unconsciousness without involving microtubules. It's
also the case that microtubules can be damaged - or effected
in
other ways - without bringing about unconsciousness.
*******************************
Some
Additional Science Stuff: Nonlocality, Etc.
Quantum
coherence
(at least in terms of microtubules, the brain and consciousness) is
the idea - or reality - that there can be “subatomic cooperation”.
In other words, there's a possibility of communication
between
subatomic elements within the brain. (Let's not get too pedantic about the word
“communication” here.)
Thus
it's the case that
nonlocality
can account for subatomic particles “knowing each other”; even
though they're separated by large distances. Can we move from that
fact to the possibility of objects (yes, which are made
up of
particles) knowing each other at large distances? More specifically,
can we say that different microtubules (embedded in neurons) can know
other microtubules at large distances? (Let's not get too pedantic
about the word “know” here.)
In
terms of microtubules, that could mean that communication occurs
between
microtubules
because of quantum superpositions.
Thus neurons themselves may be connected by virtue of the aforesaid
microtubular connections. Indeed that neuronal connectivity rides on
the back of quantum microtubular connectivity. More specifically,
quantum gravity (according to Penrose) may cause microtubular
collapse:
it is each collapse that may be responsible for each basic act (if
“act” is the correct word here) of consciousness.
Despite
these speculations about microtubular connectivity also causing
inter-neural connectivity, it's still argued that there's a problem
with the theory that happenings in single synapses have an impact on
the happenings of, say, neural assemblies.
If
there is microtubular nonlocality, then there's also microtubular
entanglement.
Or, more precisely, the subatomic particles which make up microtubules are involved in entanglement. If we move away from the
brain and their microtubules, it's certainly the case that
nonlocality and entanglement are part of the same picture and both
have been demonstrated in many experiments. What hasn't been
conclusively demonstrated is what Penrose and Hameroff have to say
on, well, microtubular nonlocality and entanglement. (That's if we
can say that it's the microtubules -, rather than their subatomic
parts - which become entangled.)
It's
also been said that entanglement and nonlocality may be applicable to
communication
systems
and
to other phenomena not directly related to the human brain.
Anton
Zeilinger,
for one, has
shown
- in his laboratories - that entangled particles can indeed be
reconstituted in different places. And, if this is the case with
artificial experiments involving laboratories, then surely it's even
more likely to be the case when it comes to the brain's microtubules... Or, indeed,
is it less
likely?
No comments:
Post a Comment