Theory of Types 1
Bertrand Russell’s theory of types seems quite commonsensical at a prima facie level.
That
is, different objects, or their many types, can't be treated in the
same way within any philosophical or logical system. In Russell’s
case, the important thing is that the predicates applicable to
different types of objects will differ depending on the type under
scrutiny. More specifically, these predicates will be true or false
of particular objects depending on the type of object that is
predicated.
In
Russell’s scheme, objects are arranged in some kind of hierarchy
from objects of the least generality to objects of the most extreme
generality. In terms of statements, this means that if predicates
change according to their types of objects, then statements will
likewise change in according to the type of objects they are
statements about. So the statements we make about individuals or
particulars can't be made about classes. Similarly, the statements we
make about classes can't be made about classes of classes. And so on
into indefiniteness.
What
of different types of individuals? Is this theory true of these types
too?Clearly, this theory has
relevance to the class of all classes that do not belong to
themselves. According to Russell, the theory of types is intended to
prevent the paradox discovered in the said class of classes. It was
said these classes both are and aren't members of themselves. The
original assertion was about classes, not classes of classes. That
is, it is said of classes that they either are or aren't members of
themselves. This part doesn't result in paradox.
For
example, the class of abstract entities is itself an abstract entity.
Therefore it's a member of itself. On the other hand, the class of
pink shoes is not a pink shoe. Therefore it's not a member of itself.
So such classes don't generate any paradoxes.
We
introduced another class that is a class of classes. It was,
therefore, of a higher logical order than first-order classes. We
talked of the class of all classes that aren't members of themselves.
This class generated a paradox: it is both a member of itself and not
a member of itself. This is the paradox that Russell attempted to
solve or prevent. How did he attempt it?
He
created his theory of types. And, according to this theory, the
predicates and statements we apply to objects depend on the nature of
the type of objects being talked about. Clearly, a class of classes
is not of the same logical order than a basic class; just as basic
classes are of a different logical order than individuals.
We've
said that classes can either be members of themselves or not members
of themselves. That’s fine. However, we also asked whether or not a
class of classes, the class of classes that aren't members of
themselves, is a member of itself. It was concluded that it both is
and isn't a member of itself. This, of course, is paradoxical. So how
does Russell’s theory prevent this paradox from occurring?
Again,
different objects have different predicates and statements made about
them. A class is a different ‘object’ than a class of classes.
It follows that we can't predicate or assert about this class of
classes the same kind of things we predicate and assert about
first-order classes. We said that the predicate ‘a member of
itself’ is either true or false of the classes that either are
members of themselves or not. However, our main concern is a class
of classes: the class of all classes that aren't members of
themselves. So we can't ask of this class the question whether or
not it's a member of itself because that kind of question can only be
made of classes, not classes of classes. And if these
questions can't be asked in the first place, then this class of
classes is not in fact paradoxical after all.
A.J.
Ayer writes that it is “nonsensical” to even ask if the class of
all classes that aren't members of themselves is itself a member or
not a member of itself. This question can only be asked of
first-order classes, not of second-order classes or classes of
classes.
The
Theory of Types 2
It's
not only classes, predicates and expressions that differ depending on
the objects they're applied to: the theory also applies to ‘numerical
expressions’. These expressions, according to Russell and/or Ayer,
change their ‘sense’ depending on whether or not they count
individuals, classes or classes of classes.
This
is an interesting use of the term ‘sense’ if we bear in mind
Frege’s notion of sense and reference and all the later theories
about reference. Usually proper names, for example, are not supposed
to have a sense. So it seems strange, prima facie, that the
theory of types claims that numerical expressions have different
senses depending on what they are applied to.
However,
it may not be numbers themselves that have different senses; but the
expressions in which they are constituents. It also seems strange
that the way we ‘count’ different types of objects will also be
different, regardless of the ‘senses’ of the numbers within the
expressions. Again, perhaps I need to know what is meant by
‘numerical expressions’ and whether such expressions have
constituents that somehow are relevant to the notion of ‘sense’.
There
is a problem with the theory of types. In traditional class theory,
the same object can belong to different classes. Though in the theory
of types, we must be careful to treat different objects in different
ways. This may result in certain classes becoming smaller than they
originally were because many classes contain different types of
objects as members. This will result in both a proliferation of
classes, and also the numerical shrinkage of the classes that are
deemed to already exist.
Though,
according to set-theory, we define the natural numbers by reference
to classes. That is, the class of all two-membered classes is in fact
the class we call the number 1. So if class membership, the
number of members, defines the natural numbers, then the shrinkage of
classes that results from the theory of types may result in their
being classes that aren't large enough - in terms of members - to
define the higher natural numbers. That is, the higher numbers may
not be able to correspond with any classes because there aren't
enough classes with correlative higher memberships. The classes
needed to account for the higher numbers may simply run out. The may
not be enough classes with higher enough memberships to account for
the higher natural numbers.
Another
way of putting the theory of types - in this class-membership and
numbers sense - is that the conditions that allow objects to belong
to certain classes becomes more stringent. Classes become better
defined, as it were. And if the conditions of class membership are
more stringent, then clearly many previous classes will effectively
become smaller in terms of their numbers of members. And, again, if
this is the case, then certain higher numbers may not find their
correlative classes in set-theory. This is clearly a problem for
set-theory and the theory of types. Rather than reject a
set-theoretic account of numbers, many logicians in Russell’s day
and after simply rejected his theory of types. Other theories, of
course, were created and adopted after the period in which Russell
formulated his theory of types.
No comments:
Post a Comment