What
I'll attempt to do in the following is summed up very well by the
American-English
philosopher
Gordon Park Baker. In his 'φιλοσοφια:
εικων και ειδος'
(which can be found in Philosophy
in Britain Today),
Baker wrote:
“We
should... make serious efforts at raising questions about the
questions commonly viewed as being genuinely philosophical. Perhaps
the proper answers to such questions are often, even if not always,
further questions!”
All
sorts of questions have been deemed to be profound, deep and worthy
of serious thought. However, perhaps it's just as important - and
indeed just as philosophical - to ask questions about these questions. Or as
Gordon Baker puts it:
“The
unexamined question is not worth answering.”
Baker
adds:
“To
accept a question as making good sense and embark on building a
philosophical theory to answer it is already to make the decisive
step in the whole investigation.”
At
the outset, however, it must be noted that what follows isn't a
defence of a position that's similar to that which was once held
by Russell, Wittgenstein or by the logical positivists. Nor is
it a defence of some of the positions advanced by “ordinary-language
philosophers”
in the 1940s, 1950s and early 1960s.
That
is, it's not being argued here that many everyday - and indeed
philosophical - statements have a “logical” or “philosophical
grammar” which somehow hides deep underneath them. Or at least it
isn't part of my argument that the logical
grammar
of (possibly) bogus questions is hidden.
On
the other hand, neither do argue that, as the late Wittgenstein put,
“nothing
is hidden”.
It's
also the case that I don't have a problem with poetic philosophical
statements. Take this two examples from Friedrich Nietzsche
(both from Beyond
Good and Evil):
“I
obviously do everything to be 'hard to understand' myself.”
“The
text has disappeared under the interpretation.”
As they stand, these sentences aren't meant to be philosophical
arguments. They're poetic and/or cultural statements. Nonetheless,
philosophical arguments or positions are still embedded within them
and can easily be eased out.
Ironically,
Wittgenstein himself certainly did see Nietzsche as a philosopher.
Indeed it can be said (it often has been said) that many of the
Wittgenstein's own statements or questions are poetic, gnomic or
“mystical” in nature.
In
addition, there's no need to use the word “nonsense” about most
(or indeed any) of the questions or statements considered in the
following piece. (Despite saying that, the word 'nonsense' wasn't
used – by philosophers – in its everyday sense: it usually had a
precise technical or philosophical meaning/usage.) For example,
saying that a particular question simply assumes
that there's an answer (or that a question can't be answered at all)
doesn't seem to be a point about
logical grammar or about nonsense...
There's
an equivocation here because in Wittgenstein's Culture
and Value (a selection from the philosopher's personal
notes), he wrote the following:
"As
long as there continues to be a verb 'to be' that looks as if it
functions in the same way as 'to eat' ... people will keep stumbling
over the same puzzling difficulties.”
Now
who can have a problem with that? That position may not be entirely
acceptable (as it stands); or it may simply be partial. However, if the
question
“What
is it like to be?”
is
asked partly (or indirectly) because questions like
“What
is it like to eat Heinz
Beanz?”
are
also asked, then there may well be a problem.
Bogus
Philosophical Questions?
All
sorts of questions can be asked. And two fundamental things are
assumed when a question is asked:
i)
That the question makes sense. (This use of the word 'sense' is meant
in a loose non-philosophical
sense.)
ii)
That the question must (or does) have an answer.
In
addition, another problem is summed up (again) by Gordon Baker:
“Questions,
just as much as assertions, carry presuppositions.”
This
is especially true in philosophy. The type of questions I primarily
have in mind here are the following.
i)
“Why does the physical give rise to consciousness?” (Or in David
Chalmers' words:
“How do physical processes give rise to experience?” )
ii)
“Why are the constants of nature the
way they are?” (Or:
“Why do the laws of physics have the numerical values they do
have?”)
Just
because a question is grammatical and even makes (some kind of) sense, that doesn't
mean that it's a philosophically (or otherwise) legitimate question.
So
firstly let's take an extreme question:
“Why
does the number 6 have such a poor sense of humour?”
Now
that's a perfectly grammatical sentence. It even makes some kind of
sense. (It does so – at least in part - precisely because it is
grammatical.) However, in a philosophical and even commonsensical
sense,
it doesn't make... well, sense.
To
back this up, let's use Noam Chomsky's well-known surreal sentence (though
not itself a question). Namely:
All
the words (as well as their concepts) in the question are “transparent”
when taken individually. (That is, if words can ever be taken
individually or outside of the “Fregean context” of a whole
sentence.) More relevantly, the sentence itself is grammatically
correct – and it may even be logically correct. (Chomsky said that
it is “semantically nonsensical”.) However, isn't it also
empirically, scientifically and even metaphysically nonsensical? (Hence Chomsky's semantic
position.) Nonetheless, can't we still understand
that statement?
Take
these questions about Chomsky's sentence:
i)
Can we conceive
of that statement being true? (The word 'conceive' is often used by
philosophers who make use of modal
notions.)
ii) Do
we need
to conceive the statement's truth-conditions in order to understand
the statement?
iii) Can
we even conceive
of a situation in which colorless green ideas sleep furiously?
Here
it seems that grammatical (or even logical) correctness runs
free of conceivability - not only of Chomsky's semantics. In other words,
perhaps we don't - and can't - actually conceive of colorless
green ideas sleeping furiously
at all. Nonetheless, the sentence can still be understood simply
because it's grammatical. Though all that, of course, depends on
precisely what's meant by the word 'understand'!
So
let's take a slightly less extreme question:
“Why
does everyone simply adore Anton Webern's Symphony Op. 21?”
That
question is also perfectly grammatical. And it's certainly not
surreal like the first question. However, the question is somewhat
bogus because it simply assumes
that everyone does love Webern's Symphony Op. 21. (Of course it's
possible
that they do.) So this is very much like this well-known question:
“When
did you stop beating your wife?”
In
other words, both questions beg
the question (i.e., they "assume the [or an] initial point").
So
the first question is rightfully deemed to be ridiculous. And the
second question begs
the question.
G.P.
Baker's Wittgensteinian Position
“...
to suppose that the answers to philosophical questions await
discovery is to presuppose that the questions themselves make sense
and stand in need of answers (not already available). Why should this
not be a fit subject for philosophical scrutiny?”
Indeed
Wittgenstein did have things to say on the nature of many
philosophical questions (both in his “early” and “late”
periods). His position is partly summed up in this
passage from Robert W.
Angelo. (It contains
a quote from Wittgenstein himself.) Thus:
“...
nonsense in the form of a question is still nonsense. Which is to say
that the question-sign... can only be rejected, not answered: 'What
is undefined is without meaning; this is a grammatical remark.'...”
In
other words, any question can be asked. And any question may be taken
to be legitimate simply because it's grammatical and also because it
makes a modicum of sense
(i.e., though only if that last word is used very loosely). All the
examples given so far may fit these categories.
So
take this question:
“Why
is water H2O?”
Or
what about this well-respected (i.e., by logicians and philosophers)
statement? -
A: This statement
[A] is false.
Another
good way of summing up the problem with these
possibly-bogus
questions (or statements) is also cited by Gordon Baker. He writes:
“Questions,
just as much as assertions, carry presuppositions. To pose a
particular question is to take things for granted, to put some things
beyond question or doubt, to treat some things as matters of
course...”
As
stated before, one obvious “presupposition” to a question is that
there's an answer to it; or at least a possible
answer.
Now
take a seemingly silly question which was first
mentioned by Bertrand Russell.
(This question is sometimes used to flesh-out issues within the
realism/anti-realism debate.) Here's my (very slight) paraphrase of
the question:
“Is
there a china teapot between the Earth and Mars which is revolving
about the sun in an elliptical orbit?”
The
presupposition
here might have been that we - even if only in
principle - could
discover the truth or falsity of this statement. (Though this wasn't Russell's
point.) Does that also work for Chomsky's earlier statement (i.e.,
“Colorless green ideas sleep furiously”)?
It's
possible that we could at least attempt to find an answer to this
tea-pot question. However (to state the obvious), we'd quickly find
out there are no green ideas. Therefore the question as to whether or
not green ideas “sleep furiously” can't (or shouldn't)
even arise. In other words, what's being presupposed
here is there are green ideas.
Now
what's being presupposed here? -
“Why
is water H2O?”
Can
the same question also be asked of this
question
from
David Chalmers? Namely:
“Why
should physical processing give rise to a rich inner life at all?”
To
repeat: a (possible) answer is being presupposed in both cases. That
is, the very asking of these questions means that the questioners
must assume that there are answers – at least answers in
principle.
To
use the words of Baker again. Aren't these questioners “taking certain
things for granted”? That is, aren't they primarily taking for granted
that their questions are legitimate and that there are answers? Moreover, aren't these questioners also “put[ting] some things beyond
question or doubt”; as well as “treat[ing] some things as matters
of course”?
[All
the possibly-bogus questions just mentioned will be tackled in
greater detail in the later parts of this piece.]
***************************
No comments:
Post a Comment