Monday, 13 January 2020

Graham Priest – and Martin Heidegger! – on Nothing (1)




i) Introduction
Nothing
ii) Nothing as Absence: Anxiety
iii) Ontological Dependence (or Grounding)
iv) Distancing
v) Standing Outside Of
vi) The Summing of No Things

Perhaps the most important way in which Graham Priest has been influenced by Martin Heidegger is the latter's view on Western logic itself. Heidegger once wrote:

If the power of the intellect in the field of inquiry into the nothing and into Being is thus shattered, then the destiny of the reign of 'logic' in philosophy is thereby decided. The idea of 'logic' itself disintegrates in the turbulence of a more original questioning.”

(Note the scare quotes around the word “logic”.)

One can see how all that poetical stuff can lead to dialetheism; which, after all, “embraces contradictions”. So whereas Heidegger appeared to hold up his hands in despair at Western philosophy (or simply reject Western philosophy in toto), Priest offers us his dialetheism as a solution to the problems which Heidegger has just articulated in the passage above.

More importaly, since Heidegger “deconstructed” Western logic, then that - almost by definition - must inevitably lead to the deconstruction of Western philosophy as a whole. (At least that would be the case if one sees Western philosophy as a Platonic Form.) Thus Heidegger's route to his Destruktion of philosophy was through the “questioning” of logic.

Heidegger, like Priest, can also be said to have been “misled” by the word “nothing” (which he turned into his “the nothing” - das Nichts). So, yes, Rudolf Carnap was right about this... And so was Wittgenstein. That is, being (philosophically) perplexed by the use of the word “nothing” led to what Wittgenstein said is “language going on holiday”. (See later essay.)

So it's also odd that Priest seems to completely reject (or possibly ignore!) everything that was said by Carnap, Wittgenstein, Russell and other philosophers about these and similar subjects.

Nothing?

Why do we name or refer to nothing?

There's nothing to hold onto. Yet, psychologically speaking, thoughts about nothing can fill (some) people with dread; as Heidegger – through Priest – will later stress. There's something psychologically (or emotionally) both propelling and appalling about it. And that's why existentialists and other philosophers – with their taste for the dramatic and poetic - found the subject of nothing (or at least nothingness) such a rich philosophical ground to mine.

Nothing as Absence: Anxiety

Priest says that “every thing” can be absent. That may be an assumption that every thing once existed, and then became absent. Of course there can be something followed by nothing; just as some argue that there could be nothing (except perhaps God!) followed by something.

So how can all things be absent if there never were things in the first place? There is a solution to this. That is, we can have all things and then we can have nothing – say, if God decided to destroy all things (though God himself would still exist). However, I don't believe that Priest had such a scenario in mind because, after all, he says “[p]hilosophers often wonder why there is something rather than nothing”. Indeed Wittgenstein once wrote: "Not how the world is, is the mystical, but that it is." (Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus 6.44) In other words, once there was nothing; and then there was something.

Priest goes one step further (or at least Heidegger did) than this by telling us that

Heidegger, indeed, claimed that one can have a direct phenomenological experience of nothing”.

Thus we need to know what Heidegger meant by our having “a direct phenomenological experience of nothing”.

Priest himself writes:

One can have direct phenomenological acquaintance with non-existent objects.”

No we can't. One can have a “direct phenomenological acquaintance” with something, and that something is taken to be a “non-existent object”. That is, we can have a phenomenological experience of, say, Sherlock Holmes; even though he's not a real person. However, we still have “acquaintance” with some things – the actors who play Holmes, our mental images of Holmes, the paintings of Holmes, etc.

So the main point of Priest's reference to our phenomenological acquaintance with non-existent objects is to state his conclusion:

Nothing is a non-existent object which we have direct phenomenological acquaintance with.

Following on from all that, the very idea of nothing (or nothingness) is hard - or even impossible - to conceive of or imagine. This means that (at least for myself) it fails David Chalmers' conceivability argument.

Chalmers claims this:

i) x is conceivable.
ii) Whatever is conceivable is possible.
iii) Therefore x is possible.

However, what if that which is conceived of isn't actually conceived of in the the first place? What if it's only the case that words about the conceived of are simply uttered?

In any case, the important point with this is that we can distinguish conceivability from imaginability. That is, even if we can't construct mental images, etc. of nothing (or nothingness), perhaps we can still conceive of nothing (or nothingness). I, for one, can't even conceive of nothing. (So this isn't similar to someone's conceiving of a million-sided object, as presented by Philip Goff.)

Can other people conceive of nothing? Do they even have intuitions about nothing or about the notion of nothingness?

Heidegger's words (as quoted by Priest) don't help. He wrote:

Does such an attachment, in which man is brought before the nothing itself, occur in human existence? This can and does occur, although rarely and only for a moment, in the fundamental mood of anxiety (Angst).”

Here Heidegger is more likely to have meant the absence of a specific object (or the absence of specific objects). After all, how can "man" be “brought before the nothing itself” - in Priest's sense of nothing? Priest is talking about the absence of all objects, not the absense of some objects or one object. For example, Heidegger's “the nothing” may be what happens when someone visits an old building and discovers that it's no longer there. Nonetheless, he's still there and so is the surrounding landscape.

Priest and Heidegger are absolutely correct: nothingness does have psychological resonances. It's just that we can't tie those resonances to anything ontological. To connect these psychological (or phenomenological) facts (or experiences) to an ontology is a kind of psychologism, in the Fregean sense.

Nonetheless, Priest doesn't always accept Heideggerian views on nothing, though he does often mention them. Thus Priest qualifies himself when he states the following:

One does not have to share Heidegger’s gothic pessimism, to agree that one can have a phenomenological experience of nothing. All you have to do is think about it.”

Despite these qualifications, Priest does then say that “[h]ere, Heidegger got it exactly right”.

Let's take the Heidegger quote again and the additional words “[a]nxiety reveals the nothing”. What does that mean? And even though anxiety is a real psychological phenomenon, how many anxious people have nothing revealed to them?

Priest continues (in a note) on the theme of absence. He writes:

Philosophers often wonder why there is something rather than nothing. However, even if there were nothing - even if everything would be entirely absent - there would be something, namely nothing.”

This is playing with words of the worst kind. (Perhaps that's why Priest mentions “fun” a couple of times in the seminar video mentioned at the end of this piece.)

Ontological Dependence (or Grounding)

Priest also seems to accept Heidegger on “grounding” or “ontological dependency”. Heidegger wrote:

If the nothing itself is to be questioned as we have been questioning it, then it must be given beforehand. We must be able to encounter it.”

And the following statement is reflected in Priest too:

The nothing is the complete negation of the totality of beings.”

As has just been said, Priest often mentions Heidegger and Hegel. And it was originally Hegel who argued (as Priest puts it) “that nothingness was the ground of reality”.

Firstly, one may ask this question:

What does it mean to say that an object “logically depends on nothingness”?

Priest's explanations/answers don't really help.

Priest says that “every object depends for being what it is on nothingness” and that “in particular [it depends on] distancing itself from nothingness”. That simply raises the same question: What do these statements mean?

Put simply, Priest argues that all objects are grounded in nothing. (Indeed everything must also be grounded in nothing.) However, Priest doesn't “like the term 'grounding'”. Instead, he believes that “'ontological dependence' is much better”. So what about this? -

i) If x is ontologically dependent on y,
ii) then y also grounds x.

In any case, Priest rightly says that “some things depend for being what they are on other things”. Yet it's whether or not some things depend for being what they are on nothing that's relevant here.

Graham Priest ontologically depends on the zygote of his parents (as Saul Kripke explained in his Naming and Necessity). But does Graham Priest depend on nothing as well? Let's use Priest's own example. He says:

The shadow of a tree depends for being what it is on the tree itself. The shadow of the tree depends on the tree in a way that the tree doesn't depend on the shadow.”

The strange thing here is that a shadow is more ontologically robust - and even more physical - than Priest's nothing. Shadows, after all, are causally related to the physical things which cause them. Is nothing causally related to physical things? Indeed even though the shadow of a tree is an epiphenomenon (like qualia?), it's still dependent on physical things.

Distancing

Here again Priest borrows from Heidegger. This time it's with Priest's notions of distancing, etc. that are Heideggerian. Thus:

In the clear night of the nothing of anxiety the original openness of beings as such arises: that they are beings – and not nothing.”

What is Priest claiming when he says that “to be a being” is to “distance [it] from nothingness”? (This is all very metaphorical.) Priest then goes on to say that a being “couldn't be a being unless it was not nothingness”. Thus:

And so to be an object depends on nothingness as something that the being distances and distinguishes itself from.”

Is this like the claim that Paul Murphy couldn't be Paul Murphy unless he had distanced himself - and distinguished himself - from cabbages and/or protons? Sure, here we have a material object (a human being) distancing - and distinguishing - himself from other material objects (cabbages and/or protons), not from nothingness. Nonetheless, can any “being” truly distinguish - and distance - itself from such a strange thing (that's just grammar) as nothingness? And if it/he/she could, what does that actually mean? Is this a psychological or an ontological distancing and distinguishing? One can accept that persons can verbally distinguish and distance themselves from anything – even from nothing. Though, ontologically, how is that distancing and distinguishing actually brought about?

Being Different From/Standing Outside of

What about any x (or any object) being different from – and standing outside - any y? Priest says:

To say what something is you have to say what it stands outside; what it's different from. This is just an application of this to the notion of being an object.”

It's hard to make sense of this. If we need to say “what [x] stands outside” of, then it stands outside everything that isn't itself. Thus must we name literally everything that's not x or which is outside x? Just a few of these things? It's true that in common parlance we define many things by what they're not. But this is a linguistic and psychological phenomenon, not an ontological phenomenon.

For example, we can say that Prime Minister Boris Johnson “stands outside” the planet Mercury and/or all fish and chip shops. That's certainly true. But what ontological or even psychological relevance does that have?

The same is true of Priest's “different from”.

Boris Johnson is different from a iron gate and/or a shopping bag. More fundamentally, he's different from all that's not Boris Johnson. Of course in a less ridiculous way we can say that “Boris is different from a good [bad] man”. But here again, where is the ontology in all this? All we have are linguistic and psychological different froms. Sure, there are ontological differences between Boris and iron gates. (There are ethical differences between Boris and other human beings.) However, which differences from – if any – are fundamental or ontologically relevant?

Having said that, all the above may be beside the point because Priest's main thesis is that Boris Johnson stands outside - and is different from – nothing/ness. The other cases just cited may be seen as being less fundamental by Priest.

Priest then moves to his notion/metaphor of distancing. He says that “to be an object a thing must ontologically depend on not being”. What's more, “[i]t's nature is constituted by standing outside nothingness, as it were”.

The last clause, “as it were”, is certainly apt here because it's hard to fathom what standing outside nothingness is. This is like being drowned in metaphor.


Nothing is neither an object - not any being at all. Nothing thus comes forward neither for itself non next to beings to which it would as it were adhere stick.”

More metaphors. And what if we have no ontological translations of Priest's Heideggerian words.

Priest then explains himself in yet more Heideggerian terms. He says:

That's an interesting metaphor for human existence: nothingness makes possible the openness of beings as such.”

This may refer to Heidegger's idea that human beings posit themselves against nothingness – or the possibility of (their own?) non-being. This seems to be a poetic expression of human beings exerting their contingent existence and putting their finger up to it. That is, we human beings (or persons) are “open” to nothingness and even open to death.

Now we have some Hegelianisms:

Nothingness doesn't merely serve as the counter-concept of being. Rather, it originally belongs to it and is central. [Nothingness is] essential and founding as such as the being of beings...”

Is this Hegelian dialectics of the following kind? -

i) Firstly we have the negative: non-being.
ii) Then the positive: being.
iii) Finally, the synthesis: becoming.

In any case, Priest argues that nothing has an active or positive quality in that it's “essential” and “founding”. Nothingness is “the being of beings”.

The Summing of No Things

Priest has a strange position on summing (as seen within the contexts discussed above). He says:

“Everything is the sum of all things. Nothingness is the sum of no things - no objects.”

How can nothingness be a “sum of no things – no objects”? Is this similar to saying that no apples can be summed to/with no oranges? Abstract objects can be summed – as in set theory or mathematics. But is nothing an abstract object? It certainly bears little relationship to sets, propositions, numbers, etc.

In addition, although nothing can be seen as an object (as well as not being an object), Priest also says that “everything is not an object”. Yet, prima facie, it seems that everything is a better candidate for being an object than nothing is.

To get back to the passage above. What is it to be the “sum of every object”? Is this an exercise in counting? Of collecting? Of joining? Or even of “fusing” (which is a word that Priest also uses in various passages)?

This gets even more problematic (or silly) when it comes to nothing. That is, what is it to “sum [] no things”? Priest even uses the words “fuse together no things”. How does that fusion actually occur? Surely in order for any x to fuse with any y (or with anything), it firstly needs to be separate from y. Does this apply to Priest's “no things” too? And how does this summing actually work?

In any case, Priest argues that when one has “the sum of no things”, we get nothing/ness. Is this equivalent to saying the following? -

If we add 0 to 0, we get 0.

In addition, Priest also classes “no things” as non-objects. Consequently:

“Nothingness is the sum of everything that isn't an object because everything is an object.”

As stated earlier, nothing[ness] is tied (by Priest) to everything. Later, however, Priest also argues that nothing[ness] both is and is not an object (his dialetheic position).

Despite what's been said, Priest states that he sees “no reason why you shouldn't have a sum of no things”. Other people, on the other hand, “normally [] assume that if a bunch of things have a fusion or a sum, then there must be some of them”. Indeed, according to Priest, that's “a standard assumption”. Again, Priest states:

“If you think there's such a thing as nothingness, it's a very natural way of defining it. [That's] because nothing is something like the absence of all things. It's precisely what you get when you put together no things. … And as I said, if you think that everything is the sum of all things, then it's natural to think that nothing is the sum of no things. that's all the summer things that aren't objects.”

In the passage just quoted, Priest brings in his whole package of ideas on nothing. He sees nothing as a thing/object; as well as not being a thing/object; he speaks about absence; and then summing. What a “jungle” we have here - even if it's not “Meinong's jungle”.

Note:

1) Some of the quoted words and passages from Graham Priest in the following are taken from the 'Everything and Nothing' seminar – a Robert Curtius Lecture of Excellence at Bonn University - which Priest gave. I relied on both the transcript and the video itself. However, I've edited a lot of what Priest says in that seminar to make it more comprehensible. For example, I remove many of the uses of the word “so”, add full stops, commas and suchlike. Hopefully, the philosophical content is kept intact. None of this applicable to the words and passages I quote which come from Priest's papers.

*) To follow: 'Graham Priest & Martin Heidegger Take the Language of “Nothing” on Holiday' and 'Graham Priest, Martin Heidegger, Dialetheism and Nothing'.

Sunday, 12 January 2020

Donald Hoffman on Consciousness, Reality... and Mathematical Models



Sorry about flogging this dead horse again.

Donald Hoffman keeps on attempting to distance himself from those New Agers who have very similar views on consciousness and "reality". How does he do that? By using the words "precise mathematical model"... again and again and again.

For example, Hoffman claims that he offers us a "precise mathematical model of agents having subjective experiences". Yet he doesn't explain that mathematical model. And neither does he explain what he means by "mathematical model" (or give any examples) in all the other cases he mentions them. Instead, he simply keeps on using the words "precise mathematical model".

Hoffman seems to believe that many philosophers are (still) Identity Theorists (in the Old Style, circa the 1950s). I would say that there are about one or two who hold that position. (I'm being rhetorical here.) I even doubt that there are that many neuroscientists who are (strict) Identity Theorists; though some anti-physicalists pretend that all neuroscientists are. (Hoffman doesn't at all tackle the existence of elminitivists.)

Hoffman's knowledge of philosophy is very poor. His philosophising is poorer still. That doesn't matter - he's a scientist (i.e., a cognitive scientist/cognitive psychologist). However, he's a scientist who not only repeatedly uses philosophical terms: he's also a scientist who's offering us a thoroughly philosophical position on consciousness and reality.


Wednesday, 8 January 2020

Is Graham Priest (a Dialetheic Logician) Both In and Not In New York?



[This is a standard introduction to all my commentaries on videos.]


When it comes to my commentaries on particular videos, only the content of - or the words within - the video itself will be discussed. That is, the commentary won't be a case of detailed research on the subject discussed or person interviewed (as one would find in an academic paper or even in an in depth article). The reason for this is that I believe that this will help both the readers of the piece and the viewers of the video – even if such readers and viewers aren't exactly newcomers to the subject discussed or the person being interviewed in the video.

************************

Some philosophers (perhaps Graham Priest himself) have argued that dialetheism isn’t a formal logic. Dialetheism, instead, is “a thesis about truth”. One can conclude from this that it must also be at least partly world-based in nature. (Hence the reference to New York in the video.) However, I don’t believe that Graham Priest’s position — or anyone’s position — is entirely world-based.

Here’s another reference to the world from Priest. He cites quantum mechanics. (Incidentally, Priest rejects the idea that the Schrödinger’s cat thought-experiment displays dialetheism-in-concreto, as it were. That is, that the cat is both alive and dead.) Priest’s own example is one of radioactive decay. He states that at the moment of decay, the atom is both integral and nonintegral. (Though couldn’t the atom be neither integral nor nonintegral when it instantaneously and spontaneously decays? Or, alternatively, at that point it may not be an atom at all.)

Priest is also open about his debt to both Hegel and Heidegger. So there’s much philosophy “behind” his logic. Indeed philosophy of a very particular kind.

Pragmatic positions and themes from the philosophy of science also provide some of Priest’s motivations — along with Buddhism.

******************

Graham Priest’s upshot (i.e., in the video, if nowhere else):

i) Arguments to support the law of noncontradiction have failed (have they?).
ii) Therefore let’s accept the conclusion of the Liar Paradox.

Alternatively put:

i) The Liar paradox hasn’t been solved.
ii) Therefore let’s embrace it and other contradictories (though not all).

Sure, I’m putting Priest’s position simply in the above. (There are “hidden premises” between i) and ii).) His position is informally and ironically put in that this isn’t a claim that Priest would ever put it in this quasi-deductive way. (As if a single premise and a conclusion can be conclusive at all.) Nonetheless, Priest does make similar bald statements in the video above (if not in the informal way I’ve expressed it). Of course in his papers he’ll go into more detail. Yet hidden among Priest’s mass of detail it can still be said that he holds these basic positions.

So, i) and ii) is also to embrace the Liar Paradox. However, there are indeed other reasons for accepting dialetheism.

Anyway, is Priest advising us to accept the arguments which conclude that we must accept the conclusion of the Liar Paradox? Or is he stating (not arguing) that we should simply accept the conclusion - full stop? Priest seems to take the latter position — at least in this video.

Priest may be correct to say that the Humean “evidence” shows us that the logical defences of the law of noncontradiction haven’t worked . But how does that alone show us that we should accept contradictions?

All this is similar to the well-known pessimistic meta-induction which states:

i) All previous scientific theories have been found wanting.
ii) Therefore that must also be true of contemporary scientific theories.

Let’s take an extreme equivalent:

i) All previous attempts to cure cancer have failed.
ii) So let’s stop attempting to cure cancer.

Conclusion

Is Priest’s dialetheic logic about the world (i.e., an ontological position) or is it about what we can — or even shouldsay about the world? If it’s the former, then Priest could indeed be both in New York and not in New York! If it’s the latter, then it’s simply a logic that can helpfully capture and formulate such things as the inconsistencies in scientific theories. Alternatively, dialetheic logic can advance the pragmatic option of seeing two contradictory positions as true — at least for the time being!

Note:

Priest offers us the following possible-worlds symbolisation of his position. He rejects the following negation. Thus:

i) ¬A is true at w iff A is false at w.
ii) ¬A is false at w iff A is true at w.

To translate:

i) It is not the case that A is true at a world if and only if A is false at that world.
ii) It is not the case that A is false at a world if and only if A is true at that world.
.





Saturday, 4 January 2020

Philip Goff Offers Us Non-Philosophical Reasons to Become Panpsychists



[This is a standard introduction to all my commentaries on videos.]


When it comes to my commentaries on particular videos, only the content of - or the words within - the video itself will be discussed. That is, the commentary won't be a case of detailed research on the subject discussed or person interviewed (as one would find in an academic paper or even in an in depth article). The reason for this is that I believe that this will help both the readers of the piece and the viewers of the video – even if such readers and viewers aren't exactly newcomers to the subject discussed or the person being interviewed in the video.

*************************

The panpsychist philosopher Philip Goff argues that panpsychism is “more likely to be true” than all the other philosophical alternatives which tackle the nature of consciousness and reality (which are connected in panpsychism). Yet panpsychism is almost entirely speculative - at least at present. It may well provide a "pleasing and coherent picture" (as Goff puts it). However, like "beauty" in physics, a theory's coherence and pleasing nature can be very misleading. (The theoretical physicist Lee Smolin says a lot about beauty-in-physics in his book The Trouble With Physics.). Hegelianism, Marxism, Kantianism, Christianity, etc. all provided pleasing and coherent pictures too - at least they did to very many people.

Goff's Ad Hominem

Goff says:

"When we're doing science or doing philosophy, then we should certainly be thinking about not which view we'd like to be true; but which view is most likely to be true."

This is a hopeless ad hominem (well, kind of) aimed at panpsychism's detractors. 

Goff claims that materialists (some may deny this is aimed exclusively at materialists and the other critics of panpsychism) shouldn't "believe what they want to believe". That is surely "against the man" and not against the argument.

Clearly (to me at least) Goff believes that various physicalists, Darwinians, scientists, etc. (or at least some of them) would "like their views to be true" and panpsychism to be false. However, we could just as easily turn Goff's ad hom on its head and aim it at panpsychists and Goff himself. That is, these people may like panpsychism to be true. After all, panpsychism is being tied to thousands of years of religious, spiritual and moral beliefs of various kinds - not least by the person (Adrian David Nelson) who interviews Goff in the video above.

As stated in parenthesis a moment ago, some may dispute the claim that Goff is aiming his ad-hom statement exclusively at the critics of panpsychism. In other words, what if Goff is expressing a "general approach" to philosophy when he talks about people wanting x to be true/false? However, in the context of what Goff says in this video - and elsewhere - about the detractors of panpsychism, I simply think this isn't the case. That is, he believes that many philosophers are emotionally against panpsychism. And, in the context of the video above, I think it's also clear that he's only targeting panpsychism's opponents.

It doesn't help either when Goff says that "materialism is dismal". Is that a philosophical comment? In addition, almost half of this video contains criticisms (right or wrong) of materialism.

So, basically, the inverse of what Goff says is the following:

"Philosopher X would like panpsychism to be false."

I suppose none of this matters if Goff's arguments work. However, it is Goff who's used this ad-hom phrase on more than one occasion.

So, yes, Goff claimed that those who're against panpsychism don't want it to be true. And then I aimed that way of thinking at Goff himself. In turn, it can be turned against my own position against Goff... Consequently, many analytic philosophers will see this as a hopeless game.

But not so quick!

One can confront the arguments and also do the psychology and sociology. Indeed the sociology and psychology may help us understand the arguments. (Having said that, most people aren't trained in sociology and psychology.)

So pointing out these motivations to believe in panpsychism (which Goff himself cites) may not be philosophy; but it may still be relevant.

Not Philosophy

Analytic philosophers like Goff who're panpsychists constitute a small subsection of panpsychists. Most other panpsychists explicitly cite their religious, spiritual and moral/political reasons for believing in panpsychism (e.g., Rudy Rucker, etc.). In addition, most people get their panpsychism from such people, not really from Goff or from any other analytic philosopher.

And Goff himself ties panpsychism to "the meaning of human existence", "human happiness", environmentalism, "our place in the universe"and states that "materialism is a pretty dismal worldview".

As it is, I neither believe materialism (as a view of reality) is “dismal” nor not dismal. To claim either is to make a similar mistake highlighted by Spinoza. He stated:

I would warn you that I do not attribute to nature either beauty or deformity, order or confusion. Only in relation to our imagination can things be called beautiful or ugly, well-ordered or confused.”

In my view, "romantic factors" constitute the primary appeal of panpsychism when it comes to most panpsychists - including Goff. The hard analytical work may well come after the fact (as it were). That's my own ad hominem, anyway. After all, Goff offers lots of moral, political and spiritual reasons as to why panpsychism is a good idea for mankind (i.e., in the video and elsewhere). And as time goes by, Goff talks more and more about this extra-philosophical stuff.

Take Goff's specific claim that panpsychism posits "a universe we fit into". In order to understand what that means, we'd require a lot of non-scientific and, I would argue, non-philosophical baggage.

Of course:

i) Philip Goff often claims that the "good things" of panpsychism are simply its byproducts.
ii) But what if Goff's panpsychism is a byproduct of his believing in these good things?

Philosophically, it may not matter either way. Well, most analytic philosophers wouldn't care either way. Though psychologically and sociologically, surely it is of some interest.

Conclusion

As stated, Goff isn't doing himself any favours in this video. In it he talks about telepathy (he accepts its possibility, which is fine as it stands), "value in the universe", the "universal mind", etc. Indeed it gets worse as the video goes on. (I was waiting for something on ley lines and astral travelling.) Of course it can be argued that the person interviewing Goff is egging him on.

Finally, I can't help thinking that Goff is helping to open the floodgates. (I just mentioned telepathy and ley lines.) What's more, many lay people seem to be very impressed that professional (analytic) philosophers are now tackling all this stuff.


Thursday, 2 January 2020

The Case Against Professor Donald Hoffman


[This is a standard introduction to all my commentaries on videos.]


When it comes to my commentaries on particular videos, only the content of - or the words within - the video itself will be discussed. That is, the commentary won't be a case of detailed research on the subject discussed or person interviewed (as one would find in an academic paper or even in an in depth article). The reason for this is that I believe that this will help both the readers of the piece and the viewers of the video – even if such readers and viewers aren't exactly newcomers to the subject discussed or the person being interviewed in the video.

********************************

I'm gonna shout a bit in the following!

I've been studying philosophy for a bit now but I must admit that I hardly understood a word of the last hour of this "interview". (This was even harder to understand than Heidegger or Derrida.) Now was that simply because what Professor Donald Hoffman and Zubin say is so damned complex and novel? Or was it because it's so damn vague, suggestive and designed to titillate?

The endless references to "the mathematics", "mathematical models" and "mathematical theorems" (as well as the compulsory reference to Godel) just seem like a cheap attempt to give what's said kudos. Hoffman is desperate to show his physics/mathematical credentials, despite holding what many would regard as various wacky position. He shows these credentials when he keeps on talking about "the maths" and "mathematical models". Yet I can't help feeling that the term "mathematical models" is being used vaguely in Hoffman's contexts and that such models don't do the work he claims they do. (I believe too that the word "model" is often overused and misused outside of physics.)

It's like saying: This can't be wacky because I keep on mentioning mathematics. These references to maths are sugarcoating the deep and vague wackery. Now that's strong, rhetorical language from me. However, I can honestly say that I've never heard such pretentious and improvisatory stuff from a professor. And you simply can't sugarcoat this wacky pill with mathematics... It may sound pleasing when stoned; but in the cold light of day, it sucks... Or at least the things said in the last 30 minutes suck. 

(The early part of the interview on evolution is interesting; though not original to Hoffman. It's about how, in evolutionary terms, a species doesn't require all the details of any given environment in order to survive and propagate - or it doesn't require "truth", as Hoffman poetically puts it.)

On a specific technical point. Panpsychism is not dualist; as Hoffman claims it is. If there is consciousness (or "intrinsic phenomenal properties") "all the way down" to the particle and all the way up to the animal brain, then how can panpsychism be dualist? There's no separation of mind and matter in panpsychism because all matter has mind (or, at the least, experience).

It would help if Zubin, the guy interviewing Hoffman, offered some criticisms of Hoffman's positions. All we seem to have in this interview is two people agreeing with each other. In addition, we also have Zubin putting the position Hoffman has just put in his own hipster way. There's way too much agreement for my liking.

Donald Hoffman on Panpsychism


This video features Donald Hoffman - and other philosophers/scientists - on panpsychism... except that the person interviewing Hoffman has to get him on track (rather than keep him on track). That is, Hoffman doesn't offer his views on panpsychism for most of the interview. Instead, he puts his position on “icons”, “interfacing”, etc.

Hoffman believes (as stated at 32:30) that there are two (only two?) forms of panpsychism – and only one of them is “dualist”. The problem is, again, I don't understand his reasons for this
Hoffman seems to confuse – and this in incredible! – (scientific) realism with dualism. That is, realists (not dualists) “believe that an electron really exists and it really does have physical properties”. He also says that these dualists believe electrons “have a unit of consciousness”, ect. (A "unit"? Why a unit?) Hence the panpsychism.

The other version of panpsychism is actually a kind of idealism. And Hoffman adds his holistic or cosmological (like Philip Goff's “cosmopsychism”?) view in which he rejects separate “agents”, etc. And then he says this is “what [he] can show mathematically”. (Here we go again!) He calls his theory “conscious realism”; which he prefers to the term "panpsychism".

Now I don't want to get bogged down with terms or which is the correct one. However, Hoffman clearly doesn't fully understand the philosophical terms he uses. That's fine; he classes himself as a “scientist”. But I do suggest that if he's going to use terms like “panpsychism”, “realism” and “dualism”, then he should do more philosophical research and talk a little less about his own “mathematical model”.

My main argument is that Hoffman is hopeless when it comes to bringing the maths together with his philosophical speculations; primarily because his knowledge of philosophy is very rudimentary.