There have been countless definitions of the word 'consciousness'. Indeed there have also
been hundreds of books on consciousness. It's a debate that's hot and
trendy. However, it's also often pointless. The main reason for this
is that people are nearly always talking about different things when
they talk about consciousness. More relevantly, they define the word
'consciousness' in very different ways. Moreover, many who talk or
write about consciousness never actually get around to defining the
word 'consciousness' at all. True, they may have their own tacit or
unexpressed pet definitions deep within their minds; though they
never explicate or articulate such definitions precisely or in any
detail.
As
a result of all this, perhaps it would be wise to adopt a
deflationary view of the word 'consciousness'. That's what the
English philosopher Kathleen Wilkes did when she
wrote that
"perhaps
'consciousness' is best seen as a sort of dummy-term like 'thing',
useful for the flexibility that is assured by its lack of specific
content".
We
can agree with Wilkes and also see the word 'consciousness' as a
bundle-term. It is so because it has so many meanings, definitions
and connotations.
Though
if the word 'consciousness' is indeed a dummy- or bundle-term, then
surely spending any time on definitions may seem a little pointless.
Then again, in the case of Wilkes' other example of the word 'thing', if we can even define that word to some degree of approximation and
detail, then surely we can do the same with 'consciousness'.
The
psychologists James Ward and Alexander Bain (writing at the end of
the 19th century and as quoted by Edward Titchener) took a strong
line against the ostensible liberalism (or pluralism) of people like
Kathleen Wilkes. Ward and Bain believed that it's precisely the fact
that the word 'consciousness' is a dummy- or bundle-term that traps
us in the mud. They
wrote:
“'Consciousness'
is the vaguest, most protean, and most treacherous of psychological
terms.”
With
words like that, one can see how it didn't take long for behaviorism
to take up its hegemonic position in psychology and philosophy in the
1920s and beyond.
In
addition, judging by Professor Ward's use of the word 'protean', one
can also conclude that not only did he believe the word
'consciousness' to be vague, he also believed that it could be made
to mean what any writer, philosopher or layperson wanted it to mean.
(Think here of the “spiritual” uses of the word 'consciousness'.)
Thus,
as a result of all this, William James (writing at roughly the same
time as Ward), didn't offer his readers a single definition of the
word 'consciousness' in his well-known book Principles of
Psychology.
Thus,
in 1913, John B. Watson had this to say (in his paper 'Psychology
as the Behaviorist Views it'):
“The time seems to
have come when psychology must discard all references to
consciousness... This suggested elimination of states of
consciousness as proper objects of investigation in themselves will
remove the barrier from psychology which exists between it and the
other sciences.”
Of
course Watson wasn't that concerned with the definitions of the word
'consciousness'. Instead he had a problem with consciousness
itself. That problem was its non-scientific status (or even its metaphysical reality). However, there's a connection here. Perhaps the definitions
of the word 'consciousness' are both so multifarious and vague
precisely because of the non-scientific (i.e., private) nature of
consciousness. If consciousness were as intersubjective a phenomenon
as a cat or a neuron, then we wouldn't have such many multifarious
and vague definitions.
Now
let's move forward to the late 20th century.
We
can also say that the spirit (if not the letter) of behaviourism was
revived by eliminative materialists.
On
the one hand, behaviourists didn't necessarily claim that
consciousness isn't a feature of the human mind; they simply believed
it to be non-scientific. Some/all eliminitive materialists (or at least
Patricia Churchland), on the other hand, believe that “consciousness
[might] go the way of 'caloric fluid' or 'vital spirit'”.
Thus some people may think that eliminitive materialists simply want
to eliminate “propositional attitudes” and the “folk
psychology” which has partly been built on them. However, they may want to eliminate consciousness (or at least references to
'consciousness') in the long run too.
This would also explain why definitions of 'consciousness' are so
vague and multifarious. Indeed, if consciousness doesn't so much as
exist (at least as it's seen by many people), then of course the
definitions of it will be vague and multifarious!
What
Consciousness Does/Seems
One
major problem with definitions of consciousness is that many
philosophers, scientists or laypersons often fixate on what may only
be a single aspect (though sometimes aspects) of consciousness and then go
on to more or less ignore – or even deny – the rest. This is one
reason why we have a vast of amount of sexy, titillating and
pseudo-scientific theories of consciousness. That is, the
philosopher, scientist or layperson overplays his angle on
consciousness seemingly without realising that it may simply be
precisely that: a single aspect.
In
extremely broad terms, this can be seen in the debate between those
who say that “consciousness is what consciousness does” and
those who say that “consciousness is how
consciousness seems”.
For
example, arguably it can be said that the philosopher David M.
Rosenthal is concerned with how
consciousness seems when
he writes (in his paper 'A
Theory of Consciousness')
the following:
“Intentional and
sensory properties constitute the most likely candidate [for a
definition of 'consciousness']; all mental states have one or the the
other.”
Of
course it can be seen that there's a small fusion here. After all,
doesn't the intentional have an impact on what
consciousness does?
Indeed the same can even be said about “sensory properties”. Don't sensory properties (or even qualia) carry
information? And if that's the case, then sensory information can result in a person doing x
rather than y.
Jerry
Fodor has also made this point (in a review
of Colin McGinn's The
Problem of Consciousness)
when he wrote the following:
“It used to be
universally taken for granted that the problem about consciousness
and the problem about intentionality are intrinsically linked: that
thought is
ipso facto
conscious, and that consciousness is ipso
facto
consciousness of some or other intentional object... concentrating on
intentionality and ignoring consciousness - has proved a remarkably
successful research strategy so far.”
On
the other hand, John Searle (in his The
Rediscovery of the Mind)
connects intentionality to consciousness. Thus:
"Only a being
that could have conscious intentional states could have intentional
states at all, and every unconscious intentional state is at least
potentially conscious... [T]here's a conceptual connection between
consciousness and intentionality that has the consequence that a
complete theory of intentionality requires an account of
consciousness.”
Rosenthal
connects the dots too. He writes:
“Of course many
mental phenomena, such as perceptual states and emotions, have both
kinds of property [the “sensory” and “intentional”]; but
other mental states exhibit only one of the two.”
As
for the former position (i.e., “consciousness is what consciousness
does”), this will elicit causal, functional, computational,
evolutionary, neuroscientific, etc. definitions of the word
'consciousness'.
It's
quite easy for the defenders of the former position to pay little -
or even no - attention to the latter... and vice versa. Thus,
immediately, we have definitions of the word 'consciousness' which
seem to be about different things. And perhaps that's because they
are
about different things!
We
can say, instead, that definitions of consciousness should include
both what
consciousness does
and how
conscious seems.
Except, of course, that we'll then be in danger of supplying
definitions which are far too long or detailed. In addition, some
believers in the idea that consciousness
is what consciousness does
reject the phenomenal (or, say, qualia) outright – or see it as
having little importance (at least to science). Similarly, those
people who stress experience, subjectivity, qualia, “what it is
like”, etc. may underplay what
consciousness does;
though, in this case at least, they're highly unlikely to ignore (or reject) the
functional, neuroscientific, etc. aspects of consciousness.
*) To follow: 'On Definitions of 'Consciousness': Examples (2)'.
No comments:
Post a Comment