Sunday, 9 April 2023

Physicist Steven Weinberg on Why Reductionism Isn’t a Bogeyman

Physicist Steven Weinberg was a rare example of a scientist who actually discussed reductionism in philosophical terms. That’s fairly strange because this is a contentious issue which is usually only discussed by philosophers and (relevantly enough) the critics of science. Weinberg’s central point was that physics — and perhaps much of science generally — has always been (at least in broad outline) reductionist. What’s more, many of those who criticise reductionism are actually criticising science itself. However, they artfully mask over that fact by overusing the word “reductionism” (as well as the words “materialism” and “scientism”).

(i) Introduction
(ii) Steven Weinberg Defends Reductionism
(iii) In Praise of Reductionism
(iv) Grand and Petty Reductionism
(v) Einstein and Grand Reductionism
(vi) Weinberg’s (Mild?) Reductionism About Chemistry
(vii) The Complete Autonomy of All the Sciences?
(viii) The Autonomy of the Special Sciences?

In a YouTube video called ‘What is Reductionism?’, the theoretical physicist and science communicator Sabine Hossenfelder describes reductionism in the following way:

“Reductionism is, loosely speaking, the idea that you can understand things by taking them apart into smaller things.”

Hossenfelder adds: “This definition of ‘reductionism’ is not quite correct, but it’s not too far off.” (This is a hint at Steven Weinberg’s “petty reductionism”, as we shall see later).

Relevantly, Hossenfelder then tells us “how enormously important reductionism is for scientific understanding”.

Hossenfelder also plays down the role of philosophy when it comes to reductionism. Firstly, she tells us that a

“lot of people seem to think that reductionism is a philosophy, but it most definitely is not that”.

Instead, reduction is a “hypothesis about the properties of nature”. What’s more:

“It is the hypothesis that has so far been supported by every single experiment that has ever been done. I cannot think of any scientific fact that is better established than that the properties of the constituents of a system determine how the system works.”

[Is a kid a reductionist when he decides to take apart his trainset — into its constituent parts — in order to find out what’s wrong with it?]

Despite Hossenfelder’s downplaying of philosophy, it’s worth noting the fact that the theoretical physicist Steven Weinberg (1933–2021) himself is a rare example of a scientist who actually discussed reductionism in philosophical terms. Indeed, he freely admitted that this is primarily a philosophical issue — unlike Hossenfelder.

To repeat. For a physicist, Weinberg wrote a fair amount on the subject of reductionism. And that’s fairly strange because this is a subject that’s usually only discussed by philosophers and the critics of science, not by scientists themselves.

[Sabine Hossenfelder is very critical of philosophy. Or, at the very least, she tells us that she’s “not interested” in it (see here). That said, I believe that she’s toned down her view on this subject in the last couple of years. I suspect that this is largely due to the strong comebacks she’s received from both philosophers and scientists on the issue of philosophy and its relation to science.]

Steven Weinberg Defends Reductionism

Steven Weinberg was a self-described “reductionist”. Or, at the very least, he was a self-described “compromising reductionist”. In Weinberg’s own words:

“I don’t consider myself an uncompromising reductionist. I consider myself a compromising reductionist.”

Whatever kind of reductionist Weinberg was, many people have a serious problem with all types of (what they call) reductionism.

So all this depends on how Weinberg compromised and who he was compromising with.

Whatever the case is, self-styled “anti-reductionists” will argue that Weinberg’s following line contradicts his compromise:

“I would like to try to formulate in what way elementary particles physics is more fundamental than other areas of physics.”

However.

Saying that “particles physics is more fundamental than other areas of physics” isn’t automatically (or necessarily) a commitment to uncompromising reductionism — or, indeed, a commitment to any kind of reductionism. In theory, then, one can believe that particle physics is indeed fundamental, at the very same time as also being against reducing other sciences down to it. That is, particle physics may well be deemed to be fundamental, and yet the scientist who believes this may still (as it were) allow the other sciences their own (complete?) “autonomy” (see later section).

In Praise of Reductionism

Steven Weinberg’s central point (like Sabine Hossenfelder’s) is that nearly all physics — and perhaps much of science generally — has always been reductionist. Indeed, reductionism has been at the heart of physics since Isaac Newton — and even well before that. (Read the extract from Weinberg’s The New York Review article in the opening image.)

What’s more, many (i.e., not all) of those who criticise (what they call) reductionism are often actually criticising science itself. However, they often artfully mask over that fact by overusing the word “reductionism” (as well as the words “scientism” and “materialism”). Indeed, if Weinberg is correct and reductionism is at the heart of physics, then criticising reductionism is almost the same as criticising science — or at least the same as criticising most of physics. (Biology often gets a lot a flack for its reductionism too — see here.)

Added to all that is Weinberg’s idea that even when it comes to complexity, emergence and the autonomy of the other sciences (i.e., outside physics), the laws of physics and its equations still (to use a non-technical term) underpin such complexity, emergence and many of the other sciences.

In terms of detail, Weinberg makes a distinction between two different scientific strategies: “grand reductionism” and “petty reductionism”.

Grand and Petty Reductionism

Firstly, Steven Weinberg defines grand reductionism thus:

“Grand reductionism is what I have been talking about so far — the view that all of nature is the way it is (with certain qualifications about initial conditions and historical accidents) because of simple universal laws, to which all other laws may in some sense be reduced.”

As for “petty reductionism”:

“Petty reductionism is the much less interesting doctrine that things behave the way they do because of the properties of their constituents: for instance, a diamond is hard because of the carbon atoms of which it is composed can fit together neatly.”

Weinberg then sums of the distinction by adding that

[g]rand and petty reductionism are often confused because much of the reductive progress in science has been in answering questions about what things are made of, but the one is very different from the other”.

Yet even Weinberg’s petty reductionism contains a large and obvious element of truth to it. That is, objects (or Weinberg’s “things”) do “behave the way they do because of the properties of their constituents” (as Sabine Hossenfelder stated in the introduction). However, few scientists would claim that a composite object (made of smaller things) could be entirely explained by — or reduced to - an individual object (or constituent part) of which it is made. Indeed, not many scientists would claim that a composite object is simply the sum of the individual things of which it is made (see ‘Mereology’). Nonetheless, it is still the case that the composite object does indeed behave the way it does — largely — because of the properties of its constituent parts. That is, if its constituents were different, then its overall behaviour would be different too.

All that said, adept philosophers could provide many convoluted thought experiments and arguments which may well demonstrate exceptions to this rule (i.e., the rule about the importance of an object’s constituents).

For example, such philosophers would argue that, in some cases at least, if you take away an individual constituent, then the composite object would still behave normally (or in its usual way). Indeed, on a functionalist account, even removing many individual constituents from a composite object may not (or will not) have a (big?) impact on the behaviour of that object. (This is obviously the case when one thinks in terms of removing, say, a few neurons from a brain or a couple of bricks from a house.)

However, the behaviour of a composite object would still be dependent on its constituents even if some — or many — of its constituents were either removed or substituted with other (material) things (as in functionalist accounts). That’s because this would simply mean that the new constituents would then need to be factored into the story of the composite object. That is, new constituents would then be the — partial - explanation of the behaviour of the composite object. Or if some — even many — constituent parts were removed, then there would still be constituents which haven't been removed. And then they would largely determine the behaviour of the composite object.

Thus, this line of reasoning means that the popular philosophical idea of multiple realizability (as in functionalism) doesn’t necessarily work against reductionism.

All that said, Weinberg still plays down petty reductionism when he continued by saying that “[p]etty reductionism is not worth a fierce defense”. He added:

“Sometimes things can be explained by studying their constituents — sometimes not.”

Albert Einstein and Grand Reductionism

Steven Weinberg offered us a concrete example of his distinction between grand reductionism and petty reductionism when he wrote the following words:

“When Einstein explained Newton’s theories of motion and gravitation, he was not committing petty reductionism. His explanation was not based on some theory about the constituents of anything, but rather on a new physical principle, the General Principle of Relativity.”

In the way Weinberg puts things, it may even be hard to decipher how a reductive strategy would work in the case of Einstein’s General Relativity. Yet, in theory at least, Einstein might well have used a reductive strategy. That is, motion and even gravitation could have, in principle, been explained in terms of a reduction of motion and gravitation to the objects which have mass and to the constituents (or geometry) of space. What’s more, even today gravity can be reduced (if not experimentally) to its (possible?) constituents — i.e., gravitons.

All that said, Einstein constructed his Relativity theories before anyone knew about the fine structure of spacetime (whether loops, foam or whatever) and gravitons. Indeed, all this knowledge might not have helped him anyway. That is, according to Weinberg, Einstein’s “principle” is painted as being purely mathematical and theoretical in nature. Put simply, because Einstein was a theoretical physicist (i.e., not an experimental or “hands-on” physicist), then the constituents of this and that didn’t really play much of a role in his General Relativity. That said, this may be too simplistic an opposition (i.e., as in the theory/experiment binary) to advance. After all, Einstein (to take just one example) had much to say about the constituent “parts” of electromagnetic waves — i.e., photons (see here).

In any case, Weinberg’s upshot is that Einstein reduced things to “simple universal laws”, not to the (physical) constituents of composite objects. However, one wonders (as already hinted at) if these two approaches can ever really exist in splendid isolation from one another — at least over long periods of scientific history.

Weinberg’s (Mild?) Reductionism About Chemistry

There’s a certain sense in which even some strong anti-reductionists would agree with Weinberg's (as it were) mild reductionism about chemistry. (Can reductionism ever be mild to the anti-reductionist?)

For example, Weinberg stated the following:

[T]here are no principles of chemistry that simply stand on their own, without needing to be explained reductively from the properties of electrons and atomic nuclei.”

This position was once (seemingly?) backed up by Paul Dirac. Weinberg himself states the following:

[Freeman Dyson] also cited the work of Schrödinger and Dirac on quantum mechanics in 1925 and 1927 as ‘triumphs of reductionism. Bewildering complexities of chemistry and physics were reduced to two lines of algebraic symbols’.”

In one respect, it’s true that Paul Dirac (1902–1984) put the quintessential (scientific) reductionist position (at least according to Murray Gell-Mann) in that his relativistic quantum-mechanical equation for the electron (of 1928) “explained most of physics and the whole of chemistry”.

Of course, the interpretation of what Dirac said himself is entirely dependent on what the word “explained” means in this context. In one sense, then, Dirac’s own position was simply factual. (Or, at the very least, the facts as he saw them.) That is, according to Gell-Mann (again), Dirac presciently realised that

[a] great many of the phenomena of chemistry are governed largely by the behavior of the electrons as they interact with the nuclei and with one another through electromagnetic effects”.

In that limited sense, Dirac was right. However, if we take Dirac to have believed that literally everything about chemistry could by explained by his equation (or even by physics generally), then that would indeed be problematic.

Now take the physicist Murray Gell-Mann’s position.

Gell-Mann agreed with Dirac’s grand claim when he wrote the following:

“QED [quantum electrodynamics] does explain, in principle, a huge amount of chemistry. It is rigorously applicable to those problems in which the heavy nuclei can be approximated as fixed point particles carrying an electric charge.”

Indeed, Gell-Mann went further when he continued:

“In principle, a theoretical physicist using QED can calculate the behavior of any chemical system in which the detailed internal structure of atomic nuclei is not important.”

If we return to Weinberg.

The Complete Autonomy of All the Sciences?

From reading Steven Weinberg, all he means by saying that the special sciences “don’t stand on their own” is that such principles and laws (to use that non-technical word again) underpin chemistry. This isn’t an argument that everything within chemistry can be explained in terms of those principles, laws and equations. (If these three things can even be distinguished at all.) However, if it weren’t for the laws, principles and equations of physics, then chemistry wouldn’t stand at all. In a strong sense, then, this is obvious. What’s more, even some anti-reductionists would agree — if only if put in these mild terms.

All that said, what Weinberg stated next will be way more controversial and problematic to many anti-reductionists. Weinberg continued:

[I]n the same way there are no principles of psychology that are freestanding, in the same sense that they do not need ultimately to be understood through the study of the human brain, which in turn must in the end be understood of the basis of physics and chemistry.”

This passage will displease — and even anger — anti-reductionists more than anything else quoted in this essay. After all, psychology is deemed to be autonomous because it’s essentially about human persons (or collections thereof), who are themselves meant to be autonomous. (See ‘Special sciences’.) Thus, any encroachment on psychology from, say, neuroscience, let alone from physics, is often deemed to be sacrilege. (The specialness of the special sciences was advanced by Jerry Fodor way back in 1974. See his paper ‘Special Sciences (or: The Disunity of Science’.)

Murray Gell-Mann goes even further than Steven Weinberg when he argued that psychology is “not yet sufficiently scientific”. What’s more, he went on to say that his

“preference would be to take [them] up in order to participate in the form of making them more scientific”.

All that said, what Weinberg himself argued (from both an anti-reductionist and a reductionist point of view) seems to be pretty harmless. That’s primarily because psychological principles do stand alone without needing to mention anything about physics (or the physics of the brain).

Yet here again Weinberg is talking about the laws, principles and equations of physics which (that word again) underpin “the human brain”, if not the science of psychology itself. (Most psychologists virtually ignore the human brain.)

Again, the principles of psychology don’t need to be understood through the “study of the human brain”, let alone on “the basics of physics and chemistry”. However, the brain is what it is because of the laws, principles and equations of physics. And psychology is what it is because of physical brains (as well as the interactions of such brains and their environments).

Despite all that, the theoretical physicist Sean Carroll often stresses the autonomy of the special sciences. (Jerry Fodor — again — stressed what he called “strong autonomy”.)

The Autonomy of the Special Sciences?

More particularly, Sean Carroll advances the autonomy of what he calls “emergent theories”. (This is an important part of his “poetic naturalism”.) Carroll writes:

“The emergent theory is autonomous [] it works by itself, without reference to other theories.”

Elsewhere, Carroll says that with strong emergence “all stories are autonomous, even incompatible”. Yet, in other places, Carroll also stresses emergent theories and their compatibility with fundamental theories. Indeed, Carroll actually hints at a lack of (complete?) autonomy when he says that “we might learn a little bit about higher levels by studying lower ones”. In addition, Steve Carroll (in a seminar) used the word “consistence” in reference to the fit between emergent and more basic theories.

So how can that consistency and compatibility — between two very different and supposedly autonomous theories — be established?

Carroll also argues that (some) emergent theories are accurate…

How is that accuracy established?

Does Carroll simply assume an accuracy that’s tacitly and essentially guaranteed by a more fundamental (or basic) theory? Thus, doesn’t Carroll himself limit the emergent theory’s supposed autonomy?

In opposition to Sean Carroll, it seems that Murray Gell-Mann didn’t believe in this (complete?) autonomy. That’s because he believed in both a “bottom-up method of building staircases between disciplines”, and a “top-down approach” as well. Yet if the higher-level disciplines were indeed truly autonomous, then why would they require either a “top-down” or a “bottom-up” method? Surely they could stand on their own two feet. Indeed, the fact that Gell-Mann even raised the question of both bottom-up and top-down approaches (or methods) means that he did indeed have a (to use his own words) “bias in what invites the charge of ‘reductionist’”. In other words, because Gell-Mann didn’t believe in the (complete?) autonomy of the special sciences, he could be classed as a reductionist — as he himself admitted. A non-reductionist, on the other hand, would say that the special sciences are completely (or genuinely) autonomous. Thus, they don’t need to account for themselves — at least not via physics.

(*) See my ‘Physicist Steven Weinberg Defended Reductionism: Mary Midgley and Gerald Edelman Attacked It’.

My flickr account and Twitter account.


Sunday, 2 April 2023

Isaac Newton’s Religious Physics?

Paul Davies (the physicist and writer of popular science) informs his fellow scientists (as well as his readers) about Isaac Newton’s religious physics.

Paul Davies and Isaac Newton

The main problem with Paul Davies’s stress on Isaac Newton’s religious beliefs, and how they influenced (or even determined) his actual physics, is that he fails to distinguish the context of discovery from the context of justification. Thus, at its crudest, it wouldn’t make the slightest bit of difference to Newton’s theories, ideas or hypotheses (i.e., in physics) whether he was a serial killer, believed in pink goblins, was a Christian fundamentalist or stole all his ideas from Leibniz.

Broadly speaking, Paul Davies’s stress on Newton’s religious beliefs is something which had just previously occurred in the national media of many countries. This (as it were) new-found interest in Newton (at least when it came to the media) was largely down to the circulation of unpublished and previously unknown documents which had been written by the 17th-century English scientist (see here).

More particularly, many commentators were very excited by the fact that Newton prophesied that the world would end in 2060!

The story about Newton’s 2060 prophesy (alongside comments on his alchemy, his fixation with numbers, his many chronologies, his interpretations of the Bible, and his takes on the “philosopher’s stone” and “sacred geometry”) was featured on the front page of the UK’s Daily Telegraph, Canada’s National Post and other national newspapers. Added to that were the many internet and television features which followed, as well as a number of documentary films.

Of course, much has also been made of Newton’s (as it were) religious credentials. What’s more, spiritual-but-not-religious people and New-Agers have also made much of Newton’s alchemy, Biblical prophesies, chronologies, fixation with numbers, interpretations of the Bible, and his takes on the philosopher’s stone and sacred geometry. Indeed, their biographical and historical detail about Newton may be largely correct too.

So what can we draw from all that?

This new hullabaloo about Newton occurred in February and March 2003. That was around four years before Davies’s article ‘Taking Science on Faith’ for the New York Times (which is the main focus of this essay).

All that said, nothing in the words above is intended to imply that Paul Davies himself doesn’t have his own original and purely physics-based angle on Newton’s (as it were) religious physics. However, it can be safely assumed that many physicists and scientists both read and watched at least some of these titillating stories and programmes about Newton — despite what Davies believes about their complete ignorance of his biography and (well) religious motivations.

Isaac Newton’s Religious Physics?

The English physicist and science writer Paul Davies uses the case of Isaac Newton to get his central point across about the (to use his own word) “faith” scientists are supposed to have in the Universe’s “immutable laws”. He wrote:

“Christians envisage God as upholding the natural order from beyond the universe, while physicists think of their laws as inhabiting an abstract transcendent realm of perfect mathematical relationships.”

But what about Isaac Newton himself?

In basic terms, Davies ties Newton’s religious views to his physics. He told us that Newton

“first got the idea of absolute, universal, perfect, immutable laws from the Christian doctrine that God created the world and ordered it in a rational way”.

Davies then concluded by saying that

[t]his shared failing is no surprise, because the very notion of physical law is a theological one in the first place”.

Davies adds that this is a “fact that makes many scientists squirm”.

It must be said that Davies is certainly correct about Newton’s religious views. And he’s also correct about how Newton himself tied his religious views to his own physics.

Take just a single example. Newton once stated the following:

“When I wrote my treatise about our System I had an eye upon such Principles as might work with considering men for the belief of a Deity and nothing can rejoice me more than to find it useful for that purpose.”

Yet all that is part of the context of discovery — as we shall see later.

Davies then (as it were) had a go at scientists for failing to see that Newton’s (to put it crudely!) physics is religious.

Davies also told us that

[h]istorians of science are well aware that Newton and his contemporaries believed that in doing science they were uncovering the divine plan for the universe in the form of its underlying mathematical order”.

Indeed, historians of science will be aware of all that. Yet not many scientists would have a problem with any of this — despite what Davies says. Of course, some (or many) of them probably wouldn’t find it very interesting - at least not from a scientific perspective. However, Davies is arguing that they should find it interesting from a scientific perspective.

In any case, Davies concluded:

“I am depressed that reminding scientists of this well-known historical fact should elicit such a shock-horror response.”

It can be strongly doubted that there has been such a “shock-horror response” from most — or even any — scientists. This is especially the case if most scientists are well aware of the context of justification and context of discovery distinction (which will be tackled in a moment). Of course, scientists needn’t use these precise or specific technical terms from the philosophy of science.

Indeed, there’s one physicist who’s neither ignorant of, nor shocked by, Newton’s (as it were) religious context. Take the case of the theoretical physicist Lee Smolin.

This is what Smolin wrote in response to Davies’s essay ‘Taking Science on Faith’:

“As Davies says, the idea of immutable eternal laws arose in Newton’s time, when science and theology were much closer together.”

Smolin even (at least partially) agreed with Davies’s central thesis when he continued in this way:

“It does seem that getting rid of this idea is a necessary step for modern science to become fully free of the 17th century theological climate in which it was born.”

Relevantly, Smolin then diverges from Davies:

“However it is an exaggeration to say that until this is done science’s claims to be ‘free of faith are bogus.’ Most of science is healthy and most scientists rely on notions of laws that are restricted to certain domains where they are well tested.”

This passage includes Smolin’s realisation that Davies continuously conflates certain physicists with scientists as a whole. What’s more, Davies isn’t even right about all physicists, as Smolin’s own physics (or philosophy of physics) shows. And so too does the position of, to take only one example, Leonard Susskind and all those other physicists who’ve raised the possibility of “local bylaws” in the Universe. (Susskind once wrote: “If these things prove true, then some features of the laws of physics (maybe most) will be local environmental facts rather than written-in-stone laws — laws that could not be otherwise.”) There are also those physicists (a fair few of them) who’ve raised the possibility that the universal constants may not be… constant after all (see here).

Added to all that is the fact that Davies is clearly wrong about most biologists and virtually all other scientists (i.e., outside physicists) when it comes to their supposed faith in immutable laws.

[See my essay ‘Physicist Paul Davies’s Faith in His Idea That Science is “Founded on Faith”’ for more on this.]

In any case, the basic problem with Davies’s position on Newton’s religious physics is that he fails to distinguish the context of discovery from the context of justification.

The Context of Discovery and Justification

It can be supposed that in a short article (i.e., ‘Taking Science on Faith’) for the New York Times (in which most of Davies words in this essay can be found), Paul Davies simply didn’t have time to say much about the discovery-justification distinction. That said, he virtually ignores it elsewhere too.

Put at its simplest. This is a distinction which can be made between the creation (or formation) of a new scientific theory, idea or hypothesis, and the justification, defense, and/or verification (or testing) of it. Thus, at its crudest, it wouldn’t make the slightest bit of difference to Newton’s theories, ideas or hypotheses whether he was a serial killer, believed in pink goblins, was a Christian fundamentalist or stole all his ideas from Leibniz.

It’s also worth stating here that virtually every scientist in Europe was a Christian and monotheist when Newton was working and writing. Thus, it would have been very strange if their religious beliefs hadn’t impacted in some way — or even in many ways — on their work.

So, basically, the context of discovery is all the stuff (from Davies or whoever) about Newton’s religious beliefs and even what he got up to in his private life.

Now if we get back to the precise nature of the discovery-justification distinction.

The philosopher Karl Popper had influential things to say about this distinction. (The terms “context of discovery” and “context of justification” are often associated with Hans Reichenbach’s work.)

Take Popper’s position as it’s expressed in the following passage (from his The Logic of Scientific Discovery):

“The initial state, the act of conceiving or inventing a theory, seems to me neither to call for logical analysis not to be susceptible of it. The question how it happens that a new idea occurs to a man — whether it is a musical theme, a dramatic conflict, or a scientific theory — may be of great interest to empirical psychology; but it is irrelevant to the logical analysis of scientific knowledge. This latter is concerned not with questions of fact [ ] but only with questions of justification or validity [ ]. Its questions are of the following kind. Can a statement be justified? And if so, how? Is it testable? Is it logically dependent on certain other statements? Or does it perhaps contradict them? [ ] Accordingly I shall distinguish sharply between the process of conceiving a new idea, and the methods and results of examining it logically.”

There are both positive and negative aspects to Popper’s influential take on the discovery-justification distinction.

For a start, one certainly doesn’t need to take the view that the context of discovery isn’t a legitimate subject for the philosophy of science. (At one point in the 20th century, this was indeed the consensus position.) Moreover, that context of discovery isn’t even all about “intuition”, “eureka moments”, “creativity”, “cultural and religious influences” and the like either.

Thus, there are problems with this distinction - as there are with all similar distinctions.

So it’s true that the distinction may be too neat and tidy. (Note that this essay isn’t about the distinction.) In Newton’s case, it isn’t the whole story that he created a theory in a particular cultural, religious and biographical context, and only then (or after) did he scientifically, epistemically and logically assess it. In other words, even at the heights of Newton’s religious enthusiasm (say, when he triumphantly tied his religion to physics or vice versa) there would have been (purely) scientific and logical aspects to his (as its sometimes put) theory formation

The central point is simply that there is a context of discovery.

Of course, Paul Davies may respond to all this by arguing that he’s tying Newton’s religious beliefs to his theories in physics in very precise and even technical ways. Thus, perhaps it would be very hard to do the same thing with Newton (possibly) being a serial killer, (possibly) believing in pink goblins, or (possibly) stealing all his ideas from Leibniz.

That said, it’s worth saying is that an artful commentator (with a knowledge of physics, history, religion, and biography) could indeed link (or tie) Newton’s (possibly) being a serial killer, (possibly) believing in pink goblins, or (possibly) stealing all his ideas from Leibniz to Newton’s actual physics (even if not as convincingly as Davies). Indeed, I could imagine a Freudian psychoanalyst doing a very good job of this kind of thing. (He or she would have a field day with Newton.)

Finally, it can be said that lots of religious people are keen to get Newton (as it were) back on board (i.e., after he was “stolen” by atheists, materialists, Rationalists, or whatnot). Yet, if we adhere to the context of justification, then it simply doesn’t matter if Newton was a (proto)Enlightenment thinker (see here) and a hard-headed Rationalist (see here), or if he was a Christian literalist (see here), a magician (see here) or even a merchant of woo (see here).

Infinite Contexts of Discovery

Paul Davies and other commentators wouldn’t place too much stress on literally every aspect of any given context of discovery.

Thus, if Newton’s Christianity or monotheism is important to his physics, then was his antipathy toward Catholics (see here), his hatred of counterfeit money, etc. important too? Of course, Paul Davies directly ties Newton’s theological ideas to his actual physics - as already stated. So perhaps my examples are unfair. However, I’m sure that an artful historian, biographer or even scientist could tie something peculiar in Newton’s private and religious life to at least something in his physics (or vice versa) if he tried hard enough.

So let’s take another admittedly extreme example to get the point across.

Many — or even all — scientists were introduced to the various sciences by particular teachers at school. Does this mean that contemporary physicists should factor in these teachers, their characters, what they said and how they said it into their actual theories in physics?

More relevantly, if religious commentators are going to stress Newton’s religious beliefs and attitudes, then they’re going to need to do a hell of a lot of picking and choosing. That’s primarily because I doubt that all Newton’s religious beliefs and attitudes will fall neatly into place in any (contemporary) religious camp.

For example, Newton rejected the Trinity, which would not be of much use to Catholics and many other Christians. (See Newton on the Trinity here.) And should commenters stress the fact that Newton believed that the Papal Office was the realisation of the Biblical predictions of the Antichrist? (See Newton on the Antichrist here.)

Newton also denied that there is such a thing as an immortal soul (see here), which would be unpalatable to most monotheists. Newton even refused the sacrament of the Anglican church, which was offered just before his death (see here). And how do contemporary Christians feel about those Deists who’ve claimed Newton for themselves (see here)?

What’s more, Newton has also been claimed by rationalists against pantheists and (religious) enthusiasts. More particularly, Newton’s science was seen to be an antidote to mysticism, religious (as it were) emotionalism and superstition. So rather than Newton being some kind of (as he’s been called) “mystic” or “magician”, his physics and theories have actually been used to counteract such things.

So, as can be seen, almost everyone wants a piece of Isaac Newton!

And that’s precisely why the discovery/justification distinction is so important, relevant and, indeed, helpful.

******************

(*) See my essays ‘Physicist Paul Davies’s Deep — or Specious! — Questions About Life, the Universe and Everything’ and ‘Physicist Paul Davies’s Faith in His Idea That Science is “Founded on Faith”’.

My flickr account and Twitter account.


Tuesday, 28 March 2023

Stephen Jay Gould and E.O. Wilson on the Fact-Value and Science-Religion Distinctions

Stephen Jay Gould’s neat, tidy and sharp separation of values from facts, as well as religion from science, can itself be seen as an expression of his own political values. Rhetorically, Gould’s idea of what religion is seems to have been a product of his own imagination. And, in that imagination, religion completely abided by Gould’s own political sensitivities. Perhaps, then, it was only Gould’s view that religion should “keep[] itself away from science’s turf”, not that it has actually done so.

(i) Introduction
(ii) Fact and Value: Science and Religion
(iii) E.O. Wilson on Deriving an Ought From an Is
(iv) Where Do Values Come From?
(v) The Is-Ought Gap

In his book Rocks of Ages: Science and Religion in the Fullness of Life, the American palaeontologist, evolutionary biologist and historian of science Stephen Jay Gould (1941–2002) argued that science and religion are what he called “nets”. Science is a net which captures certain phenomena. And religion is a different net which captures very different phenomena.

Moreover, these nets have

“a legitimate magisterium, or domain of teaching authority, and the two domains do not overlap”.

It will be argued that Gould is telling us what should be, not what is. Rhetorically, then, Gould’s idea of what religion is seems to have been a product of his own imagination. And, in that imagination, religion completely abided by his own political and diplomatic sensitivities.

Fact and Value: Science and Religion

In the following passage, Stephen Jay Gould went into some detail about the fact-value distinction as it applies to science and religion:

“Science tries to document the factual character of the natural world, and to develop theories that coordinate and explain these facts. Religion, on the other hand, operates in the equally important, but utterly different, realm of human purposes, meanings, and values — subjects that the factual domain of science might illuminate, but can never resolve.”

It almost seems like a statement of the obvious to say that it is outright false to claim that religion restricts itself to “human purposes, meanings, and values”. Religion has also had tons to say (as well as do) about “the factual character of the natural world”. (Do I really need to give examples here?)

Gould’s claim that religion and science are “two magisteria [which] do not overlap” clearly ignores the fact that religion (or religions in the plural) has had very much to say on facts and physical reality. His claims also ignore (or simply play down) the fact that the many and various miracles of religion are supposed to have impacted on physical reality in very specific ways. In addition, prayers are also believed to have concrete effects on the physical world.

The British evolutionary biologist and author Richard Dawkins (see note at the end of this essay) expressed his more abstract position on Gould’s fact (science)-value (religion) distinction in the following:

[I]t is completely unrealistic to claim, as Gould and many others do, that religion keeps itself away from science’s turf, restricting itself to morals and values.”

Dawkins added:

“A universe with a supernatural presence would be a fundamentally and qualitatively different kind of universe from one without. The difference is, inescapably, a scientific difference. Religions make existence claims, and this means scientific claims.”

It is simply false to claim that religion has kept itself to itself, not only “unrealistic”.

So surely what Gould claimed is actually normative, rather than factual.

Perhaps, then, it was Gould’s view that religion should “keep[] itself away from science’s turf”, not that it actually has done so, and will continue to do so in the future. It certainly hasn’t done so in the past. And, clearly, that’s still the case today…

Indeed, isn’t all this obviously the case?

Gould also stated the following:

“‘Do we violate any moral codes when we use genetic technology to place a gene from one creature into the genome of another species?’ represent questions in the domain of values.”

This passage just seems so categorical and dichotomous. A student wouldn’t get away with writing it.

Perhaps Gould did get away with this philosophical ineptitude because his prose style is so literary, and therefore hard to pin down. (Many commentators have praised Gould’s writing style. See Analysis of Stephen Jay Gould’s Writing Style’.) Perhaps it’s also because Gould was so highly regarded as a scientist.

However, the statements above (from Gould) are not themselves scientific. His comments on the neat, tidy and sharp separation of facts from values (or vice versa), and science from religion, can themselves be seen as an expression of Gould’s political values.

Gould’s NOMA (“non-overlapping magisteria”) idea is also extremely artificial. Indeed, it’s a position driven by a desire for political diplomacy.

[Gould once wrote: “Religion is too important to too many people for any dismissal or denigration of the comfort still sought by many folks from theology.”]

In detail. Even if there is no role for scientific (or sociological, psychological, evolutionary, etc.) scrutiny and data on the nature of values, then why should we accept (or trust) anything any religion has to say on it? This isn’t to reject religion’s input out of hand. However, Gould either/or religion/science binary is so crude that it must surely have the consequence that science is automatically excluded from any input on the nature of values — as least values as expressed by religion (or by religions).

And what about philosophy and other forms of critical thinking which are neither scientific nor religious? After all, Gould’s NOMA idea is itself neither scientific nor religious — it’s primarily political.

Moreover, what if the sciences do have something to say on the values we’ve adopted about gene transferal (Gould’s own example) or about any other subject? And what about the evolutionary origins of our values and ethics?

Sure, scientists may well make incorrect claims on these issues. Yet scientists make correct claims too. However, Gould’s neat, tidy and political division leaves no role for any science when it comes to religious values.

[I suspect that Gould might have denied this last claim when expressed in that simple and categorical way. He might have argued — or implied — that there is a role for science when it comes to values… as long as that role doesn’t involve the strong criticism of religion.]

And what about the “moral codes” which Gould said that scientists and others “violate”? What if they are pernicious moral codes? What if they are historically contingent or tribal moral codes?

In these cases, then, the sciences can help with the moral codes themselves, not just with the “facts”.

So what can evolutionary theory and the sciences generally tell us about values and morals?

As British science writer and journalist Matt Ridley puts it (see here), morals involve human behavior, which is observable. And what is observable is open to scientific scrutiny.

Some religious people may now respond by arguing that many claims in evolutionary theory aren’t (always?) based on anything that’s literally (or obviously) observable. They will also stress the theoretical nature of many claims about evolution itself.

In addition, a distinction can be made, and will be made, between the human expressions of values and moral positions, and their abstract or religious (as it were) reality. That is, according to religious people (or monotheists), values and moral truths exist timelessly in the mind of God. And according to some philosophers (such as moral realists), values and moral truths exist timelessly in some abstract space (or domain), and even in the concrete world itself, without having any necessary connection to either God or religion.

To sum up. The core of Gould’s NOMA idea is a consequence of his somewhat naive belief in a chasm (or at least large gap) between fact and value.

Now E.O. Wilson provides an interesting counterpoint to Gould on the fact-value distinction, if not also on the science-religion distinction.

E.O. Wilson on Deriving an Ought From an Is

Some readers may agree with the following passage from Daniel Dennett:

“If ‘ought’ cannot be derived from ‘is,’ just what can ‘ought’ be derived from? Is ethics an entirely ‘autonomous’ field of inquiry? Does it float, untethered to facts from any other discipline or tradition? Do our moral intuitions arise from some inexplicable ethics module implanted in our brains (or our ‘hearts,’ to speak with tradition)?”

In tune with the Dennett passage above, one can say that if the ought (or values) can’t be derived from “facts” (or from the scientific is), then religious values (at least) must indeed be completely autonomous. Indeed, perhaps we can’t derive values from any other domain. (Except, perhaps, philosophy or personal whim.)

The passage from Dennett also squares fairly well with E.O. Wilson’s position.

Edward Osborne Wilson (1929–2021) was an American biologist and naturalist. Wilson has been called “the father of sociobiology”. (He has also been called “the father of biodiversity” for his environmental advocacy.)

E.O. Wilson attempted to provide a scientific account of what he called “ethics”, if not what Gould called “values”. In addition, Wilson seemed to believe that an ought can be derived from an is, which Gould clearly didn’t believe.

[Various philosophers have offered us very intricate examples and analyses of how an ought can be derived from an is — see here. However, none of them seem to bear much of a relation to Gould’s position on religion and values.]

If religion is truly an autonomous “magisterium”, then its values can’t be derived from scientific facts or, indeed, from what is (i.e., not anything outside the religious what is).

That said, whereas Gould’s NOMA (i.e., “non-overlapping magisteria”) fails because it is primarily political in nature, Wilson’s position fails because his overall position on the is-ought distinction is (I believe) philosophically flawed.

[Wilson, in turn, believed that philosophy is a waste of time primarily because he — like many physicists and other scientists — believed that all philosophers ignore all science. See here.]

More relevantly, E.O. Wilson took almost the exact opposite position to Gould.

Whereas Gould demanded that science must keep out of the magisterium of religion, and that religion must keep out of the magisterium of science, Wilson believed that values and ethics (if not religion itself) are the sole domain of science.

It’s not surprising, then, that someone who believed in (universal) scientific consilience should have believed that ethics (if not religion) is a suitable subject for scientific scrutiny. (Consilience:the principle that evidence from independent, unrelated sources can ‘converge’ on strong conclusions”.)

[It’s interesting, and not coincidental, that there were both scientific and political conflicts between Gould and Wilson. In fact, it can be argued — and many people have — that the scientific conflicts were largely political in nature, at least on Gould’s part. See here and here.]

Where Do Values Come From?

So how did E.O. Wilson explain science’s relatively new interest in ethics? Wilson argued:

“The objective meaning of ethical precepts comprises the mental processes that assemble them and the genetic and cultural histories by which they evolved. Those who think that an is/ought gap exists have not reasoned through the way the gap is filled by mental process and history.”

So what do the words “the objective meaning of ethical precepts” mean?… Actually, it’s fairly clear what Wilson was getting at. Still, it’s an odd use of the words “the objective meaning of”.

Clearly, Wilson was offering what he took to be a purely descriptive position on “ethical precepts”, not a normative one. Perhaps it follows from this (at least to some people) that it’s not ethics at all. Instead, it’s simply the scientific study of human ethics…

Wilson might well have dismissed that just-stated distinction.

In more detail, Wilson’s position can be seen as being purely scientific. That’s primarily because of statements such as the following:

[E]thical precepts comprises the mental processes that assemble them and the genetic and cultural histories by which they evolved.”

These passages are about what we (whoever “we” are) have taken ethical precepts to be — not what ethical precepts are or what they should be. In that sense, then, it can be argued that Wilson’s position isn’t ethics at all. It’s the scientific (i.e., biological, neuroscientific, psychological, sociological, historical, etc.) study of human ethics.

Again, Wilson might well have taken these distinctions to be entirely bogus.

Yet isn’t ethics about how we should live, not how we have lived and how we do live?

More concretely, if Wilson believed that ethics is the study of the “genetic and cultural histories by which [ethical precepts] evolved”, then perhaps we can’t do much (or even anything) about such causal aetiologies of our ethical standards and principles. That’s the case because such things have already happened.

So is this is simply a causal account of what we believe and do in the ethical sphere?

As already stated, perhaps the study of the “mental process that assemble [our ethical precepts]” isn’t itself in the domain of ethics.

The Is-Ought Gap

Is the is/ought gap (or is-ought problem) bridged simply by reasoning about this “mental process and history”?

And is all this still in the magisterium of the is and was, not in the magisterium of the ought?

In detail. Even if we can fill in the gap (as Wilson put it) between the original causes of our beliefs and principles and the beliefs and principles themselves which followed, then does that bridging alone take us into the normative (or from the is to the ought) ? By filling in the causal gaps between causes and their effects (ethical precepts in Wilson’s book), then perhaps we still don’t move from the is to the ought (or from the descriptive to the normative).

So it’s still unclear why Wilson believed that the is/ought gap has been (or can be) bridged or “filled’ in the way he outlined.

To repeat. How will acquiring knowledge of the causes of our ethical precepts tell us whether or not our precepts are the right or the wrong ones? The causal or scientific facts of genetics (or whatever scientific data we can find or use) may indeed help us understand why we hold our ethical precepts. However, surely such facts alone can’t tell us why we should still hold them.

The English philosopher, writer and journalist Julian Baggini (1968 — ) sees some of these problems too. He writes:

“The idea here seems to be that ethical precepts — for example, the incest taboo — have their roots in particular genetic and cultural histories. It is clear that understanding such histories will be a useful tool in making ethical judgements. What is less clear is that this is a way out of the is/ought problem.”

We will indeed learn much from the aetiology of the incest taboo. However, we won’t learn whether or not that taboo is right or wrong from studying its “roots in particular genetic and cultural histories”. This knowledge, of course, may (again) help us in other ways. It will tell us, for example, that the taboo wasn’t passed down from heaven or that it’s not a non-natural precept which we somehow “intuit”. What’s more, all that scientific knowledge may — or will — indeed have an effect on our “ethical judgements”. However, that knowledge will not, at least not on its own, determine the conclusions of our ethical judgements…

So what will?

Wilson seems to have argued that we can indeed derive what we ought to do from what is (or what was) the case. That is, if something is genetically and/or culturally inscribed, then it must be a correct ethical precept…

Yet that clearly doesn’t follow.

What’s more, Wilson himself probably wouldn’t have accepted that this was his position when expressed in that categorical and simple way.

Our natural instincts, for example, may be bad instincts. As Baggini (again) puts it when he argues that

“we will do well to struggle to behave in ways that might seem contrary to our natural instincts, as, for example, with respect to ethical precepts rooted in a mistrust of strangers or in aggression responses”.

Of course certain natural instincts may also be good instincts. So it all just depends…

*********************

(*) See my essay ‘Stephen Jay Gould on Science and Religion: The Politics of Non-Overlapping Magisteria’.

Notes:

(1) Many people have a (to use the Reverend Ian Paisley’s words about his attitude toward Catholics) “perfect hate” of Richard Dawkins. This is hardly surprising when one considers the fact that religion had a “hegemonic” political, moral and social position for millennia — as Stephen Jay Gould himself noted. And Dawkins strongly criticises that hegemonic entity which Gould says people feel strongly about. (Gould: “Religion is too important to too many people for any dismissal or denigration [].”) Thus, people feel strongly about Dawkins largely because he criticises the religion they feel strongly about.

(2) Stephen Jay Gould wrote:

[] I also know that souls represent a subject outside the magisterium of science. My world cannot prove or disprove such a notion, and the concept of souls cannot threaten or impact my domain. Moreover, while I cannot personally accept the Catholic view of souls, I surely honor the metaphorical value of such a concept both for grounding moral discussion and for expressing what we most value about human potentiality: our decency, care, and all the ethical and intellectual struggles that the evolution of consciousness imposed upon us.”

There’s a problem here. Religious people (Catholics in this case) do not see souls as having “metaphorical value”. They believe that souls are real or that they (well) exist. They also believe the the nature of souls is truthfully expressed in religious texts — and what is expressed in them bears no resemblance to what Gould says about them. In that sense, then, Gould’s view of souls can be deemed to be both insulting and condescending to religious people. Indeed, his view is also like “the God of the philosophers” in that it bears little resemblance to (as it were) the God of the people.

Of course, Gould might have replied to these accusations by saying that only to him are souls (as it were) metaphorical entities. In that case, then, when Gould discussed souls with religious people (if he ever did), then wouldn’t both parties have been talking about two different things or even talking passed each other?

My flickr account and Twitter account.